梅核气吃什么药最好| 上海什么时候解放的| 农历是什么生肖| 颈动脉强回声斑块是什么意思| 生理盐水是什么水| 湿疹是因为什么引起的| 清明节吃什么好| chihiro是什么意思| 2月20号是什么星座| 绿意盎然是什么意思| 九月三日是什么纪念日| 下肢浮肿是什么原因引起的| 什么样的伤口需要打破伤风针| 今日立冬吃什么| 慢性胃炎是什么原因引起的| 嗓子痒干咳吃什么药| 皮内瘤变到底是什么意思| 1997年属牛的是什么命| 博士和博士后有什么区别| 霸屏是什么意思| 青霉素v钾片治什么病| 女人为什么喜欢坏男人| 眉毛里面有痣代表什么| dw手表是什么档次| 排斥是什么意思| 吃什么可以提高免疫力| 最毒妇人心是什么意思| 市局副局长什么级别| 喝枸杞子泡水有什么好处和坏处| 长期喝蜂蜜水有什么好处| 朋友生日送什么礼物| 恍恍惚惚什么意思| impress是什么意思| 佐助是什么意思| 霖五行属什么| 渃是什么意思| 家里消毒杀菌用什么好| 什么食物含碘| 翌日什么意思| 商是什么| 献血前要注意什么| 中心句是什么意思| 胃反流有什么症状| 流年是什么| 接地气是什么意思| 鸽子吃什么粮食| 庙会是什么意思| 硬下疳是什么意思| 什么是大小周| lbl是什么意思| 豆腐是什么意思| 手术后吃什么补品好| 什么虎不吃人| 迁移宫是什么意思| 亚洲没有什么气候| 复古红是什么颜色| 1月21是什么星座| 什么布料最好| 什么是腐女| 脑缺血灶是什么意思| ds什么意思| 社区建档需要什么资料| 失聪是什么意思| 仙人掌什么时候开花| 生理期为什么会肚子疼| 耳鸣是什么原因造成的| 夏天吃什么解暑| 果子狸携带什么病毒| 传导阻滞是什么意思| 女人什么时候排卵| 什么品牌蓝牙耳机好| 脚底褪皮是什么原因| 3月20日什么星座| 阳痿早泄是什么原因| 什么手表品牌最好| 感冒吃什么药好得快| 先天性一个肾对人有什么影响| 静待花开什么意思| 头发一把一把的掉是什么原因| 肾阳虚有什么症状男性| 前庭大腺囊肿是什么原因引起的| 日字旁和什么有关| 公历和农历有什么区别| 什么叫多巴胺| 含金量什么意思| 美国为什么不敢动朝鲜| 少校是什么级别| 天经地义的意思是什么| 两个夫一个车是什么字| 什么牙膏好| 沙茶酱什么味道| 双肺纹理增多模糊是什么意思| 肝火旺盛是什么意思| 因数是什么意思| 34岁属什么| 勇气是什么| 甲功六项检查什么| 举足轻重是什么意思| 脖子粗挂什么科| 软蛋是什么意思| 打磨工为什么没人干| 鲱鱼罐头为什么这么臭| 带黄金对身体有什么好处| 百香果有什么功效| 非分之想是什么意思| 女人依赖男人说明什么| 小孩子手脚脱皮是什么原因| lhrh是什么激素| 褪黑素有什么副作用| 排卵期和排卵日有什么区别| 林深时见鹿是什么意思| 狗可以吃什么| 湾仔码头水饺为什么贵| 用什么泡脚能减肥| 史努比是什么意思| 干火重吃什么药管用| 产后42天复查都检查什么| henry是什么意思| 金木水火土各代表什么| 训练有素是什么意思| 今年83岁属什么生肖| 藿香正气水什么牌子的好| 现在去贵州穿什么衣服| circle是什么意思| 核医学科主要治什么病| 割包皮有什么好处和坏处| 宫商角徵羽是什么意思| 脾胃虚弱能吃什么水果| 画面感是什么意思| 山药吃了有什么好处| 什么可以治早泄| 滑膜炎是什么原因引起的| 领证需要准备什么| 闰六月给父母买什么| 左旋延胡索乙素是什么| 情分是什么意思| 心存善念是什么意思| 杨颖是什么脸型| 什么是碱性磷酸酶高怎么回事| 66是什么意思| 飞龙在天是什么生肖| 梦见数字是什么意思| 拉杆箱什么材质的好| 什么是宫颈纳囊| 多吃蒜有什么好处和坏处| 馥字五行属什么| 对等是什么意思| 4月10日是什么星座| 心身医学科是看什么病| 乳糖不耐受吃什么药| 免疫缺陷是什么意思| 红萝卜不能和什么一起吃| 什么三什么四| 炒木耳为什么会炸锅| 心肌酶高是什么意思| 嫌恶是什么意思| 男士检查精子挂什么科| evian是什么品牌| 人力资源是什么意思| 梦见自己准备结婚是什么意思| 年检是什么意思| 结婚30年是什么婚姻| 古人的婚礼在什么时间举行| 止汗药什么最好| 骨质疏松吃什么药好| 月的偏旁有什么字| 幼儿园什么时候报名| 梦见自己被抢劫了预示什么| 镭射是什么| 氯雷他定片什么时候吃| 菠萝炒什么好吃| 喉咙痛用什么药好得快| 狗的本命佛是什么佛| 小番茄有什么营养价值| 什么颜色衣服最防晒| 六月一日什么星座| 血糖高初期有什么症状| 热感冒吃什么食物好| 什么是u| 什么是绩效工资| 什么的北京城| 系鞋带什么意思| 京剧红色脸谱代表什么| 拉屎酸臭是什么原因| 膻味是什么意思| 胸膜炎是什么症状| 新生儿什么时候可以喝水| 桃花是什么季节开的| 抱怨是什么意思| 口臭睡觉流口水什么原因| 头发为什么会分叉| 18年属什么生肖| 0x00000024蓝屏代码是什么意思| 垂体是什么| 耳朵一直痒是什么原因| 专升本有什么专业| 妈妈是什么| 痔疮痒痒的是什么原因| gucci中文叫什么牌子| 荨麻疹什么症状| om什么意思| 什么是69式| 铁锈是什么颜色的| 血小板为0意味着什么| 李莫愁的徒弟叫什么| 眼睛看东西模糊是什么原因| 国防部长是什么级别| 排卵期后面是什么期| 吃什么药能冲开宫腔粘连| 总胆红素高是什么意思| 男性什么适合长期泡水喝| 什么是性上瘾| 太阳一晒脸就红是什么原因| 恍然大悟是什么意思| 盆腔炎做什么检查能查出来| 血凝是什么意思| 葡式蛋挞为什么叫葡式| 男女接吻有什么好处| 农历六月六日是什么节日| 去医院要带什么| 今天什么时候出梅| 月经量少什么原因| 后生可畏是什么意思| rinnai是什么品牌| 淋巴细胞低是什么原因| 渡人渡己什么意思| 紫癜是什么病严重吗| 85属什么| 什么的东西| 丰的部首是什么偏旁| 泥灸是什么| 通奸是什么意思| 六味地黄丸是治什么病| 梦到女朋友出轨是什么意思| 海参为什么越小越贵| 固本培元什么意思| 鼻咽炎有什么症状| 口干舌燥吃点什么药| 癫痫属于什么科| 吃什么补脾胃| 观音菩萨属什么生肖| 孕妇建档需要什么资料| 血管瘤是什么病| 热裤是什么裤子| 尿酸高喝什么茶| 蜘蛛的天敌是什么动物| 心衰竭吃什么药效果好| 糖尿病什么水果不能吃| 进产房吃什么补充体力| 炖鸡汤放什么材料好吃| 河南话信球是什么意思| 三伏贴是什么| 十二指肠炎吃什么药| 壬午日五行属什么| 虎的偏旁是什么| 女生diy什么意思| 腹泻吃什么消炎药| 双子座和什么星座最不配| 香油是什么油| fob价格是什么意思| 言过其实是什么意思| dbm是什么单位| 6月7号是什么星座| 做乳腺彩超挂什么科| 百度Jump to content

尼尔机械纪元2b小姐姐果体爆衣MOD 无圣光版v2.0

This is a good article. Click here for more information.
Page semi-protected
From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
百度 FAST早期科学数据中心副主任刘志杰说,经过一年多的紧张调试,FAST已实现跟踪、漂移扫描等多种观测模式,调试进展超过国际同类大型望远镜,成为世界级的“观天利器”。

Coin showing the owl of Athena
The owl of Athena, a symbol of knowledge in the Western world

Knowledge is an awareness of facts, a familiarity with individuals and situations, or a practical skill. Knowledge of facts, also called propositional knowledge, is often characterized as true belief that is distinct from opinion or guesswork by virtue of justification. While there is wide agreement among philosophers that propositional knowledge is a form of true belief, many controversies focus on justification. This includes questions like how to understand justification, whether it is needed at all, and whether something else besides it is needed. These controversies intensified in the latter half of the 20th century due to a series of thought experiments called Gettier cases that provoked alternative definitions.

Knowledge can be produced in many ways. The main source of empirical knowledge is perception, which involves the usage of the senses to learn about the external world. Introspection allows people to learn about their internal mental states and processes. Other sources of knowledge include memory, rational intuition, inference, and testimony.[a] According to foundationalism, some of these sources are basic in that they can justify beliefs, without depending on other mental states. Coherentists reject this claim and contend that a sufficient degree of coherence among all the mental states of the believer is necessary for knowledge. According to infinitism, an infinite chain of beliefs is needed.

The main discipline investigating knowledge is epistemology, which studies what people know, how they come to know it, and what it means to know something. It discusses the value of knowledge and the thesis of philosophical skepticism, which questions the possibility of knowledge. Knowledge is relevant to many fields like the sciences, which aim to acquire knowledge using the scientific method based on repeatable experimentation, observation, and measurement. Various religions hold that humans should seek knowledge and that God or the divine is the source of knowledge. The anthropology of knowledge studies how knowledge is acquired, stored, retrieved, and communicated in different cultures. The sociology of knowledge examines under what sociohistorical circumstances knowledge arises, and what sociological consequences it has. The history of knowledge investigates how knowledge in different fields has developed, and evolved, in the course of history.

Definitions

Knowledge is a form of familiarity, awareness, understanding, or acquaintance. It often involves the possession of information learned through experience[1] and can be understood as a cognitive success or an epistemic contact with reality, like making a discovery.[2] Many academic definitions focus on propositional knowledge in the form of believing certain facts, as in "I know that Dave is at home".[3] Other types of knowledge include knowledge-how in the form of practical competence, as in "she knows how to swim", and knowledge by acquaintance as a familiarity with the known object based on previous direct experience, like knowing someone personally.[4]

Knowledge is often understood as a state of an individual person, but it can also refer to a characteristic of a group of people as group knowledge, social knowledge, or collective knowledge.[5] Some social sciences understand knowledge as a broad social phenomenon that is similar to culture.[6] The term may further denote knowledge stored in documents like the "knowledge housed in the library"[7] or the knowledge base of an expert system.[8] Knowledge is closely related to intelligence, but intelligence is more about the ability to acquire, process, and apply information, while knowledge concerns information and skills that a person already possesses.[9]

The word knowledge has its roots in the 12th-century Old English word cnawan, which comes from the Old High German word gecnawan.[10] The English word includes various meanings that some other languages distinguish using several words.[11] In ancient Greek, for example, four important terms for knowledge were used: epistēmē (unchanging theoretical knowledge), technē (expert technical knowledge), mētis (strategic knowledge), and gnōsis (personal intellectual knowledge).[12] The main discipline studying knowledge is called epistemology or the theory of knowledge. It examines the nature of knowledge and justification, how knowledge arises, and what value it has. Further topics include the different types of knowledge and the limits of what can be known.[13]

Despite agreements about the general characteristics of knowledge, its exact definition is disputed. Some definitions only focus on the most salient features of knowledge to give a practically useful characterization.[14] Another approach, termed analysis of knowledge, tries to provide a theoretically precise definition by listing the conditions that are individually necessary and jointly sufficient,[15] similar to how chemists analyze a sample by seeking a list of all the chemical elements composing it.[16] According to a different view, knowledge is a unique state that cannot be analyzed in terms of other phenomena.[17] Some scholars base their definition on abstract intuitions while others focus on concrete cases[18] or rely on how the term is used in ordinary language.[19] There is also disagreement about whether knowledge is a rare phenomenon that requires high standards or a common phenomenon found in many everyday situations.[20]

Analysis of knowledge

Venn diagram of justified true belief
The definition of knowledge as justified true belief is often discussed in the academic literature.

An often-discussed definition characterizes knowledge as justified true belief. This definition identifies three essential features: it is (1) a belief that is (2) true and (3) justified.[21][b] Truth is a widely accepted feature of knowledge. It implies that, while it may be possible to believe something false, one cannot know something false.[23][c] That knowledge is a form of belief implies that one cannot know something if one does not believe it. Some everyday expressions seem to violate this principle, like the claim that "I do not believe it, I know it!" But the point of such expressions is usually to emphasize one's confidence rather than denying that a belief is involved.[25]

The main controversy surrounding this definition concerns its third feature: justification.[26] This component is often included because of the impression that some true beliefs are not forms of knowledge, such as beliefs based on superstition, lucky guesses, or erroneous reasoning. For example, a person who guesses that a coin flip will land heads usually does not know that even if their belief turns out to be true. This indicates that there is more to knowledge than just being right about something.[27] These cases are excluded by requiring that beliefs have justification for them to count as knowledge.[28] Some philosophers hold that a belief is justified if it is based on evidence, which can take the form of mental states like experience, memory, and other beliefs. Others state that beliefs are justified if they are produced by reliable processes, like sensory perception or logical reasoning.[29]

Venn diagram of justified true belief that does not amount to knowledge
The Gettier problem is grounded in the idea that some justified true beliefs do not amount to knowledge.

The definition of knowledge as justified true belief came under severe criticism in the 20th century, when epistemologist Edmund Gettier formulated a series of counterexamples.[30] They purport to present concrete cases of justified true beliefs that fail to constitute knowledge. The reason for their failure is usually a form of epistemic luck: the beliefs are justified but their justification is not relevant to the truth.[31] In a well-known example, someone drives along a country road with many barn facades and only one real barn. The person is not aware of this, stops in front of the real barn by a lucky coincidence, and forms the justified true belief that they are in front of a barn. This example aims to establish that the person does not know that they are in front of a real barn, since they would not have been able to tell the difference.[32] This means that it is a lucky coincidence that this justified belief is also true.[33]

According to some philosophers, these counterexamples show that justification is not required for knowledge[34] and that knowledge should instead be characterized in terms of reliability or the manifestation of cognitive virtues. Another approach defines knowledge in regard to the function it plays in cognitive processes as that which provides reasons for thinking or doing something.[35] A different response accepts justification as an aspect of knowledge and include additional criteria.[36] Many candidates have been suggested, like the requirements that the justified true belief does not depend on any false beliefs, that no defeaters[d] are present, or that the person would not have the belief if it was false.[38] Another view states that beliefs have to be infallible to amount to knowledge.[39][e] A further approach, associated with pragmatism, focuses on the aspect of inquiry and characterizes knowledge in terms of what works as a practice that aims to produce habits of action.[41] There is still very little consensus in the academic discourse as to which of the proposed modifications or reconceptualizations is correct, and there are various alternative definitions of knowledge.[42]

Types

A common distinction among types of knowledge is between propositional knowledge, or knowledge-that, and non-propositional knowledge in the form of practical skills or acquaintance.[43][f] Other distinctions focus on how the knowledge is acquired and on the content of the known information.[45]

Propositional

Photo of the Totius Latinitatis Lexicon by Egidio Forcellini, a multi-volume Latin dictionary
Declarative knowledge can be stored in books.

Propositional knowledge, also referred to as declarative and descriptive knowledge, is a form of theoretical knowledge about facts, like knowing that "2 + 2 = 4". It is the paradigmatic type of knowledge in analytic philosophy.[46] Propositional knowledge is propositional in the sense that it involves a relation to a proposition. Since propositions are often expressed through that-clauses, it is also referred to as knowledge-that, as in "Akari knows that kangaroos hop".[47] In this case, Akari stands in the relation of knowing to the proposition "kangaroos hop". Closely related types of knowledge are know-wh, for example, knowing who is coming to dinner and knowing why they are coming.[48] These expressions are normally understood as types of propositional knowledge since they can be paraphrased using a that-clause.[49][g]

Propositional knowledge takes the form of mental representations involving concepts, ideas, theories, and general rules. These representations connect the knower to certain parts of reality by showing what they are like. They are often context-independent, meaning that they are not restricted to a specific use or purpose.[51] Propositional knowledge encompasses both knowledge of specific facts, like that the atomic mass of gold is 196.97 u, and generalities, like that the color of leaves of some trees changes in autumn.[52] Because of the dependence on mental representations, it is often held that the capacity for propositional knowledge is exclusive to relatively sophisticated creatures, such as humans. This is based on the claim that advanced intellectual capacities are needed to believe a proposition that expresses what the world is like.[53]

Non-propositional

Photograph of someone riding a bicycle
Knowing how to ride a bicycle is one form of non-propositional knowledge.

Non-propositional knowledge is knowledge in which no essential relation to a proposition is involved. The two most well-known forms are knowledge-how (know-how or procedural knowledge) and knowledge by acquaintance.[54] To possess knowledge-how means to have some form of practical ability, skill, or competence,[55] like knowing how to ride a bicycle or knowing how to swim. Some of the abilities responsible for knowledge-how involve forms of knowledge-that, as in knowing how to prove a mathematical theorem, but this is not generally the case.[56] Some types of knowledge-how do not require a highly developed mind, in contrast to propositional knowledge, and are more common in the animal kingdom. For example, an ant knows how to walk even though it presumably lacks a mind sufficiently developed to represent the corresponding proposition.[53][h]

Knowledge by acquaintance is familiarity with something that results from direct experiential contact.[58] The object of knowledge can be a person, a thing, or a place. For example, by eating chocolate, one becomes acquainted with the taste of chocolate, and visiting Lake Taupō leads to the formation of knowledge by acquaintance of Lake Taupō. In these cases, the person forms non-inferential knowledge based on first-hand experience without necessarily acquiring factual information about the object. By contrast, it is also possible to indirectly learn a lot of propositional knowledge about chocolate or Lake Taupō by reading books without having the direct experiential contact required for knowledge by acquaintance.[59] The concept of knowledge by acquaintance was first introduced by Bertrand Russell. He holds that knowledge by acquaintance is more basic than propositional knowledge since to understand a proposition, one has to be acquainted with its constituents.[60]

A priori and a posteriori

The distinction between a priori and a posteriori knowledge depends on the role of experience in the processes of formation and justification.[61] To know something a posteriori means to know it based on experience.[62] For example, by seeing that it rains outside or hearing that the baby is crying, one acquires a posteriori knowledge of these facts.[63] A priori knowledge is possible without any experience to justify or support the known proposition.[64] Mathematical knowledge, such as that 2 + 2 = 4, is traditionally taken to be a priori knowledge since no empirical investigation is necessary to confirm this fact. In this regard, a posteriori knowledge is empirical knowledge while a priori knowledge is non-empirical knowledge.[65]

The relevant experience in question is primarily identified with sensory experience. Some non-sensory experiences, like memory and introspection, are often included as well. Some conscious phenomena are excluded from the relevant experience, like rational insight. For example, conscious thought processes may be required to arrive at a priori knowledge regarding the solution of mathematical problems, like when performing mental arithmetic to multiply two numbers.[66] The same is the case for the experience needed to learn the words through which the claim is expressed. For example, knowing that "all bachelors are unmarried" is a priori knowledge because no sensory experience is necessary to confirm this fact even though experience was needed to learn the meanings of the words "bachelor" and "unmarried".[67]

It is difficult to explain how a priori knowledge is possible and some empiricists deny it exists. It is usually seen as unproblematic that one can come to know things through experience, but it is not clear how knowledge is possible without experience. One of the earliest solutions to this problem comes from Plato, who argues that the soul already possesses the knowledge and just needs to recollect, or remember, it to access it again.[68] A similar explanation is given by Descartes, who holds that a priori knowledge exists as innate knowledge present in the mind of each human.[69] A further approach posits a special mental faculty responsible for this type of knowledge, often referred to as rational intuition or rational insight.[70]

Others

Various other types of knowledge are discussed in the academic literature. In philosophy, "self-knowledge" refers to a person's knowledge of their own sensations, thoughts, beliefs, and other mental states. A common view is that self-knowledge is more direct than knowledge of the external world, which relies on the interpretation of sense data. Because of this, it is traditionally claimed that self-knowledge is indubitable, like the claim that a person cannot be wrong about whether they are in pain. However, this position is not universally accepted in the contemporary discourse and an alternative view states that self-knowledge also depends on interpretations that could be false.[71] In a slightly different sense, self-knowledge can also refer to knowledge of the self as a persisting entity with certain personality traits, preferences, physical attributes, relationships, goals, and social identities.[72][i]

Metaknowledge is knowledge about knowledge. It can arise in the form of self-knowledge but includes other types as well, such as knowing what someone else knows or what information is contained in a scientific article. Other aspects of metaknowledge include knowing how knowledge can be acquired, stored, distributed, and used.[74]

Common knowledge is knowledge that is publicly known and shared by most individuals within a community. It establishes a common ground for communication, understanding, social cohesion, and cooperation.[75] General knowledge encompasses common knowledge but also includes knowledge that many people have been exposed to but may not be able to immediately recall.[76] Common knowledge contrasts with domain knowledge or specialized knowledge, which belongs to a specific domain and is only possessed by experts.[77]

Situated knowledge is knowledge specific to a particular situation.[78] It is closely related to practical or tacit knowledge, which is learned and applied in specific circumstances. This especially concerns certain forms of acquiring knowledge, such as trial and error or learning from experience.[79] In this regard, situated knowledge usually lacks a more explicit structure and is not articulated in terms of universal ideas.[80] The term is often used in feminism and postmodernism to argue that many forms of knowledge are not absolute but depend on the concrete historical, cultural, and linguistic context.[78]

Explicit knowledge is knowledge that can be fully articulated, shared, and explained, like the knowledge of historical dates and mathematical formulas. It can be acquired through traditional learning methods, such as reading books and attending lectures. It contrasts with tacit knowledge, which is not easily articulated or explained to others, like the ability to recognize someone's face and the practical expertise of a master craftsman. Tacit knowledge is often learned through first-hand experience or direct practice.[81]

Cognitive load theory distinguishes between biologically primary and secondary knowledge. Biologically primary knowledge is knowledge that humans have as part of their evolutionary heritage, such as knowing how to recognize faces and speech and many general problem-solving capacities. Biologically secondary knowledge is knowledge acquired because of specific social and cultural circumstances, such as knowing how to read and write.[82]

Knowledge can be occurrent or dispositional. Occurrent knowledge is knowledge that is actively involved in cognitive processes. Dispositional knowledge, by contrast, lies dormant in the back of a person's mind and is given by the mere ability to access the relevant information. For example, if a person knows that cats have whiskers then this knowledge is dispositional most of the time and becomes occurrent while they are thinking about it.[83]

Many forms of Eastern spirituality and religion distinguish between higher and lower knowledge. They are also referred to as para vidya and apara vidya in Hinduism or the two truths doctrine in Buddhism. Lower knowledge is based on the senses and the intellect. It encompasses both mundane or conventional truths as well as discoveries of the empirical sciences.[84] Higher knowledge is understood as knowledge of God, the absolute, the true self, or the ultimate reality. It belongs neither to the external world of physical objects nor to the internal world of the experience of emotions and concepts. Many spiritual teachings stress the importance of higher knowledge to progress on the spiritual path and to see reality as it truly is beyond the veil of appearances.[85]

Sources

Photos of the five senses
Perception relies on the senses to acquire knowledge.

Sources of knowledge are ways in which people come to know things. They can be understood as cognitive capacities that are exercised when a person acquires new knowledge.[86] Various sources of knowledge are discussed in the academic literature, often in terms of the mental faculties responsible. They include perception, introspection, memory, inference, and testimony. However, not everyone agrees that all of them actually lead to knowledge. Usually, perception or observation, i.e. using one of the senses, is identified as the most important source of empirical knowledge.[87] Knowing that a baby is sleeping is observational knowledge if it was caused by a perception of the snoring baby. However, this would not be the case if one learned about this fact through a telephone conversation with one's spouse. Perception comes in different modalities, including vision, sound, touch, smell, and taste, which correspond to different physical stimuli.[88] It is an active process in which sensory signals are selected, organized, and interpreted to form a representation of the environment. This leads in some cases to illusions that misrepresent certain aspects of reality, like the Müller-Lyer illusion and the Ponzo illusion.[89]

Introspection is often seen in analogy to perception as a source of knowledge, not of external physical objects, but of internal mental states. A traditionally common view is that introspection has a special epistemic status by being infallible. According to this position, it is not possible to be mistaken about introspective facts, like whether one is in pain, because there is no difference between appearance and reality. However, this claim has been contested in the contemporary discourse and critics argue that it may be possible, for example, to mistake an unpleasant itch for a pain or to confuse the experience of a slight ellipse for the experience of a circle.[90] Perceptual and introspective knowledge often act as a form of fundamental or basic knowledge. According to some empiricists, they are the only sources of basic knowledge and provide the foundation for all other knowledge.[91]

Memory differs from perception and introspection in that it is not as independent or basic as they are since it depends on other previous experiences.[92] The faculty of memory retains knowledge acquired in the past and makes it accessible in the present, as when remembering a past event or a friend's phone number.[93] It is generally seen as a reliable source of knowledge. However, it can be deceptive at times nonetheless, either because the original experience was unreliable or because the memory degraded and does not accurately represent the original experience anymore.[94][j]

Knowledge based on perception, introspection, and memory may give rise to inferential knowledge, which comes about when reasoning is applied to draw inferences from other known facts.[96] For example, the perceptual knowledge of a Czech stamp on a postcard may give rise to the inferential knowledge that one's friend is visiting the Czech Republic. This type of knowledge depends on other sources of knowledge responsible for the premises. Some rationalists argue for rational intuition as a further source of knowledge that does not rely on observation and introspection. They hold for example that some beliefs, like the mathematical belief that 2 + 2 = 4, are justified through pure reason alone.[97]

Photograph of a person giving testimony
Knowledge by testimony relies on statements given by other people, like the testimony given at a trial.

Testimony is often included as an additional source of knowledge that, unlike the other sources, is not tied to one specific cognitive faculty. Instead, it is based on the idea that one person can come to know a fact because another person talks about this fact. Testimony can happen in numerous ways, like regular speech, a letter, a newspaper, or a blog. The problem of testimony consists in clarifying why and under what circumstances testimony can lead to knowledge. A common response is that it depends on the reliability of the person pronouncing the testimony: only testimony from reliable sources can lead to knowledge.[98]

Limits

The problem of the limits of knowledge concerns the question of which facts are unknowable.[99] These limits constitute a form of inevitable ignorance that can affect both what is knowable about the external world as well as what one can know about oneself and about what is good.[100] Some limits of knowledge only apply to particular people in specific situations while others pertain to humanity at large.[101] A fact is unknowable to a person if this person lacks access to the relevant information, like facts in the past that did not leave any significant traces. For example, it may be unknowable to people today what Caesar's breakfast was the day he was assassinated but it was knowable to him and some contemporaries.[102] Another factor restricting knowledge is given by the limitations of the human cognitive faculties. Some people may lack the cognitive ability to understand highly abstract mathematical truths and some facts cannot be known by any human because they are too complex for the human mind to conceive.[103] A further limit of knowledge arises due to certain logical paradoxes. For instance, there are some ideas that will never occur to anyone. It is not possible to know them because if a person knew about such an idea then this idea would have occurred at least to them.[104][k]

There are many disputes about what can or cannot be known in certain fields. Religious skepticism is the view that beliefs about God or other religious doctrines do not amount to knowledge.[106] Moral skepticism encompasses a variety of views, including the claim that moral knowledge is impossible, meaning that one cannot know what is morally good or whether a certain behavior is morally right.[107] An influential theory about the limits of metaphysical knowledge was proposed by Immanuel Kant. For him, knowledge is restricted to the field of appearances and does not reach the things in themselves, which exist independently of humans and lie beyond the realm of appearances. Based on the observation that metaphysics aims to characterize the things in themselves, he concludes that no metaphysical knowledge is possible, like knowing whether the world has a beginning or is infinite.[108]

There are also limits to knowledge in the empirical sciences, such as the uncertainty principle, which states that it is impossible to know the exact magnitudes of certain certain pairs of physical properties, like the position and momentum of a particle, at the same time.[109] Other examples are physical systems studied by chaos theory, for which it is not practically possible to predict how they will behave since they are so sensitive to initial conditions that even the slightest of variations may produce a completely different behavior. This phenomenon is known as the butterfly effect.[110]

Bust of Pyrrho of Elis
Pyrrho was one of the first philosophical skeptics.

The strongest position about the limits of knowledge is radical or global skepticism, which holds that humans lack any form of knowledge or that knowledge is impossible. For example, the dream argument states that perceptual experience is not a source of knowledge since dreaming provides unreliable information and a person could be dreaming without knowing it. Because of this inability to discriminate between dream and perception, it is argued that there is no perceptual knowledge of the external world.[111][l] This thought experiment is based on the problem of underdetermination, which arises when the available evidence is not sufficient to make a rational decision between competing theories. In such cases, a person is not justified in believing one theory rather than the other. If this is always the case then global skepticism follows.[112] Another skeptical argument assumes that knowledge requires absolute certainty and aims to show that all human cognition is fallible since it fails to meet this standard.[113]

An influential argument against radical skepticism states that radical skepticism is self-contradictory since denying the existence of knowledge is itself a knowledge-claim.[114] Other arguments rely on common sense[115] or deny that infallibility is required for knowledge.[116] Very few philosophers have explicitly defended radical skepticism but this position has been influential nonetheless, usually in a negative sense: many see it as a serious challenge to any epistemological theory and often try to show how their preferred theory overcomes it.[117] Another form of philosophical skepticism advocates the suspension of judgment as a form of attaining tranquility while remaining humble and open-minded.[118]

A less radical limit of knowledge is identified by fallibilists, who argue that the possibility of error can never be fully excluded. This means that even the best-researched scientific theories and the most fundamental common-sense views could still be subject to error. Further research may reduce the possibility of being wrong, but it can never fully exclude it. Some fallibilists reach the skeptical conclusion from this observation that there is no knowledge but the more common view is that knowledge exists but is fallible.[119] Pragmatists argue that one consequence of fallibilism is that inquiry should not aim for truth or absolute certainty but for well-supported and justified beliefs while remaining open to the possibility that one's beliefs may need to be revised later.[120]

Structure

The structure of knowledge is the way in which the mental states of a person need to be related to each other for knowledge to arise.[121] A common view is that a person has to have good reasons for holding a belief if this belief is to amount to knowledge. When the belief is challenged, the person may justify it by referring to their reason for holding it. In many cases, this reason depends itself on another belief that may as well be challenged. An example is a person who believes that Ford cars are cheaper than BMWs. When their belief is challenged, they may justify it by claiming that they heard it from a reliable source. This justification depends on the assumption that their source is reliable, which may itself be challenged. The same may apply to any subsequent reason they cite.[122] This threatens to lead to an infinite regress since the epistemic status at each step depends on the epistemic status of the previous step.[123] Theories of the structure of knowledge offer responses for how to solve this problem.[122]

Diagram showing the differences between foundationalism, coherentism, and infinitism
Foundationalism, coherentism, and infinitism are theories of the structure of knowledge. The black arrows symbolize how one belief supports another belief.

Three traditional theories are foundationalism, coherentism, and infinitism. Foundationalists and coherentists deny the existence of an infinite regress, in contrast to infinitists.[122] According to foundationalists, some basic reasons have their epistemic status independent of other reasons and thereby constitute the endpoint of the regress.[124] Some foundationalists hold that certain sources of knowledge, like perception, provide basic reasons. Another view is that this role is played by certain self-evident truths, like the knowledge of one's own existence and the content of one's ideas.[125] The view that basic reasons exist is not universally accepted. One criticism states that there should be a reason why some reasons are basic while others are not. According to this view, the putative basic reasons are not actually basic since their status would depend on other reasons. Another criticism is based on hermeneutics and argues that all understanding is circular and requires interpretation, which implies that knowledge does not need a secure foundation.[126]

Coherentists and infinitists avoid these problems by denying the contrast between basic and non-basic reasons. Coherentists argue that there is only a finite number of reasons, which mutually support and justify one another. This is based on the intuition that beliefs do not exist in isolation but form a complex web of interconnected ideas that is justified by its coherence rather than by a few privileged foundational beliefs.[127] One difficulty for this view is how to demonstrate that it does not involve the fallacy of circular reasoning.[128] If two beliefs mutually support each other then a person has a reason for accepting one belief if they already have the other. However, mutual support alone is not a good reason for newly accepting both beliefs at once. A closely related issue is that there can be distinct sets of coherent beliefs. Coherentists face the problem of explaining why someone should accept one coherent set rather than another.[127] For infinitists, in contrast to foundationalists and coherentists, there is an infinite number of reasons. This view embraces the idea that there is a regress since each reason depends on another reason. One difficulty for this view is that the human mind is limited and may not be able to possess an infinite number of reasons. This raises the question of whether, according to infinitism, human knowledge is possible at all.[129]

Value

Sculpture showing a torch being passed form one person to another
Los portadores de la antorcha (The Torch-Bearers) – sculpture by Anna Hyatt Huntington symbolizing the transmission of knowledge from one generation to the next (Ciudad Universitaria, Madrid, Spain)

Knowledge may be valuable either because it is useful or because it is good in itself. Knowledge can be useful by helping a person achieve their goals. For example, if one knows the answers to questions in an exam one is able to pass that exam or by knowing which horse is the fastest, one can earn money from bets. In these cases, knowledge has instrumental value.[130] Not all forms of knowledge are useful and many beliefs about trivial matters have no instrumental value. This concerns, for example, knowing how many grains of sand are on a specific beach or memorizing phone numbers one never intends to call. In a few cases, knowledge may even have a negative value. For example, if a person's life depends on gathering the courage to jump over a ravine, then having a true belief about the involved dangers may hinder them from doing so.[131]

Photo of early childhood education in Ziway, Ethiopia
The value of knowledge plays a key role in education for deciding which knowledge to pass on to the students.

Besides having instrumental value, knowledge may also have intrinsic value. This means that some forms of knowledge are good in themselves even if they do not provide any practical benefits. According to philosopher Duncan Pritchard, this applies to forms of knowledge linked to wisdom.[132] It is controversial whether all knowledge has intrinsic value, including knowledge about trivial facts like knowing whether the biggest apple tree had an even number of leaves yesterday morning. One view in favor of the intrinsic value of knowledge states that having no belief about a matter is a neutral state and knowledge is always better than this neutral state, even if the value difference is only minimal.[133]

A more specific issue in epistemology concerns the question of whether or why knowledge is more valuable than mere true belief.[134] There is wide agreement that knowledge is usually good in some sense but the thesis that knowledge is better than true belief is controversial. An early discussion of this problem is found in Plato's Meno in relation to the claim that both knowledge and true belief can successfully guide action and, therefore, have apparently the same value. For example, it seems that mere true belief is as effective as knowledge when trying to find the way to Larissa.[135] According to Plato, knowledge is better because it is more stable.[136] Another suggestion is that knowledge gets its additional value from justification. One difficulty for this view is that while justification makes it more probable that a belief is true, it is not clear what additional value it provides in comparison to an unjustified belief that is already true.[137]

The problem of the value of knowledge is often discussed in relation to reliabilism and virtue epistemology.[138] Reliabilism can be defined as the thesis that knowledge is reliably formed true belief. This view has difficulties in explaining why knowledge is valuable or how a reliable belief-forming process adds additional value.[139] According to an analogy by philosopher Linda Zagzebski, a cup of coffee made by a reliable coffee machine has the same value as an equally good cup of coffee made by an unreliable coffee machine.[140] This difficulty in solving the value problem is sometimes used as an argument against reliabilism.[141] Virtue epistemology, by contrast, offers a unique solution to the value problem. Virtue epistemologists see knowledge as the manifestation of cognitive virtues. They hold that knowledge has additional value due to its association with virtue. This is based on the idea that cognitive success in the form of the manifestation of virtues is inherently valuable independent of whether the resulting states are instrumentally useful.[142]

Acquiring and transmitting knowledge often comes with certain costs, such as the material resources required to obtain new information and the time and energy needed to understand it. For this reason, an awareness of the value of knowledge is crucial to many fields that have to make decisions about whether to seek knowledge about a specific matter. On a political level, this concerns the problem of identifying the most promising research programs to allocate funds.[143] Similar concerns affect businesses, where stakeholders have to decide whether the cost of acquiring knowledge is justified by the economic benefits that this knowledge may provide, and the military, which relies on intelligence to identify and prevent threats.[144] In the field of education, the value of knowledge can be used to choose which knowledge should be passed on to the students.[145]

Science

The scientific approach is usually regarded as an exemplary process of how to gain knowledge about empirical facts.[146] Scientific knowledge includes mundane knowledge about easily observable facts, for example, chemical knowledge that certain reactants become hot when mixed together. It also encompasses knowledge of less tangible issues, like claims about the behavior of genes, neutrinos, and black holes.[147]

A key aspect of most forms of science is that they seek natural laws that explain empirical observations.[146] Scientific knowledge is discovered and tested using the scientific method.[m] This method aims to arrive at reliable knowledge by formulating the problem in a clear way and by ensuring that the evidence used to support or refute a specific theory is public, reliable, and replicable. This way, other researchers can repeat the experiments and observations in the initial study to confirm or disconfirm it.[149] The scientific method is often analyzed as a series of steps that begins with regular observation and data collection. Based on these insights, scientists then try to find a hypothesis that explains the observations. The hypothesis is then tested using a controlled experiment to compare whether predictions based on the hypothesis match the observed results. As a last step, the results are interpreted and a conclusion is reached whether and to what degree the findings confirm or disconfirm the hypothesis.[150]

The empirical sciences are usually divided into natural and social sciences. The natural sciences, like physics, biology, and chemistry, focus on quantitative research methods to arrive at knowledge about natural phenomena.[151] Quantitative research happens by making precise numerical measurements and the natural sciences often rely on advanced technological instruments to perform these measurements and to setup experiments. Another common feature of their approach is to use mathematical tools to analyze the measured data and formulate exact and general laws to describe the observed phenomena.[152]

The social sciences, like sociology, anthropology, and communication studies, examine social phenomena on the level of human behavior, relationships, and society at large.[153] While they also make use of quantitative research, they usually give more emphasis to qualitative methods. Qualitative research gathers non-numerical data, often with the goal of arriving at a deeper understanding of the meaning and interpretation of social phenomena from the perspective of those involved.[154] This approach can take various forms, such as interviews, focus groups, and case studies.[155] Mixed-method research combines quantitative and qualitative methods to explore the same phenomena from a variety of perspectives to get a more comprehensive understanding.[156]

The progress of scientific knowledge is traditionally seen as a gradual and continuous process in which the existing body of knowledge is increased at each step. This view has been challenged by some philosophers of science, such as Thomas Kuhn, who holds that between phases of incremental progress, there are so-called scientific revolutions in which a paradigm shift occurs. According to this view, some basic assumptions are changed due to the paradigm shift, resulting in a radically new perspective on the body of scientific knowledge that is incommensurable with the previous outlook.[157][n]

Scientism refers to a group of views that privilege the sciences and the scientific method over other forms of inquiry and knowledge acquisition. In its strongest formulation, it is the claim that there is no other knowledge besides scientific knowledge.[159] A common critique of scientism, made by philosophers such as Hans-Georg Gadamer and Paul Feyerabend, is that the fixed requirement of following the scientific method is too rigid and results in a misleading picture of reality by excluding various relevant phenomena from the scope of knowledge.[160]

History

The history of knowledge is the field of inquiry that studies how knowledge in different fields has developed and evolved in the course of history. It is closely related to the history of science, but covers a wider area that includes knowledge from fields like philosophy, mathematics, education, literature, art, and religion. It further covers practical knowledge of specific crafts, medicine, and everyday practices. It investigates not only how knowledge is created and employed, but also how it is disseminated and preserved.[161]

Before the ancient period, knowledge about social conduct and survival skills was passed down orally and in the form of customs from one generation to the next.[162] The ancient period saw the rise of major civilizations starting about 3000 BCE in Mesopotamia, Egypt, India, and China. The invention of writing in this period significantly increased the amount of stable knowledge within society since it could be stored and shared without being limited by imperfect human memory.[163] During this time, the first developments in scientific fields like mathematics, astronomy, and medicine were made. They were later formalized and greatly expanded by the ancient Greeks starting in the 6th century BCE. Other ancient advancements concerned knowledge in the fields of agriculture, law, and politics.[164]

Photo of a replica of the printing press created by Johannes Gutenberg
The invention of the printing press in the 15th century greatly expanded access to written materials.

In the medieval period, religious knowledge was a central concern, and religious institutions, like the Catholic Church in Europe, influenced intellectual activity.[165] Jewish communities set up yeshivas as centers for studying religious texts and Jewish law.[166] In the Muslim world, madrasa schools were established and focused on Islamic law and Islamic philosophy.[167] Many intellectual achievements of the ancient period were preserved, refined, and expanded during the Islamic Golden Age from the 8th to 13th centuries.[168] Centers of higher learning were established in this period in various regions, like Al-Qarawiyyin University in Morocco,[169] the Al-Azhar University in Egypt,[170] the House of Wisdom in Iraq,[171] and the first universities in Europe.[172] This period also saw the formation of guilds, which preserved and advanced technical and craft knowledge.[173]

In the Renaissance period, starting in the 14th century, there was a renewed interest in the humanities and sciences.[174] The printing press was invented in the 15th century and significantly increased the availability of written media and general literacy of the population.[175] These developments served as the foundation of the Scientific Revolution in the Age of Enlightenment starting in the 16th and 17th centuries. It led to an explosion of knowledge in fields such as physics, chemistry, biology, and the social sciences.[176] The technological advancements that accompanied this development made possible the Industrial Revolution in the 18th and 19th centuries.[177] In the 20th century, the development of computers and the Internet led to a vast expansion of knowledge by revolutionizing how knowledge is stored, shared, and created.[178][o]

In various disciplines

Religion

Knowledge plays a central role in many religions. Knowledge claims about the existence of God or religious doctrines about how each one should live their lives are found in almost every culture.[180] However, such knowledge claims are often controversial and are commonly rejected by religious skeptics and atheists.[181] The epistemology of religion is the field of inquiry studying whether belief in God and in other religious doctrines is rational and amounts to knowledge.[182] One important view in this field is evidentialism, which states that belief in religious doctrines is justified if it is supported by sufficient evidence. Suggested examples of evidence for religious doctrines include religious experiences such as direct contact with the divine or inner testimony when hearing God's voice.[183] Evidentialists often reject that belief in religious doctrines amounts to knowledge based on the claim that there is not sufficient evidence.[184] A famous saying in this regard is due to Bertrand Russell. When asked how he would justify his lack of belief in God when facing his judgment after death, he replied "Not enough evidence, God! Not enough evidence."[185]

However, religious teachings about the existence and nature of God are not always seen as knowledge claims by their defenders. Some explicitly state that the proper attitude towards such doctrines is not knowledge but faith. This is often combined with the assumption that these doctrines are true but cannot be fully understood by reason or verified through rational inquiry. For this reason, it is claimed that one should accept them even though they do not amount to knowledge.[181] Such a view is reflected in a famous saying by Immanuel Kant where he claims that he "had to deny knowledge in order to make room for faith."[186]

Distinct religions often differ from each other concerning the doctrines they proclaim as well as their understanding of the role of knowledge in religious practice.[187] In both the Jewish and the Christian traditions, knowledge plays a role in the fall of man, in which Adam and Eve were expelled from the Garden of Eden. Responsible for this fall was that they ignored God's command and ate from the tree of knowledge, which gave them the knowledge of good and evil. This is seen as a rebellion against God since this knowledge belongs to God and it is not for humans to decide what is right or wrong.[188] In the Christian literature, knowledge is seen as one of the seven gifts of the Holy Spirit.[189] In Islam, "the Knowing" (al-?Alīm) is one of the 99 names reflecting distinct attributes of God. The Qur'an asserts that knowledge comes from Allah and the acquisition of knowledge is encouraged in the teachings of Muhammad.[190]

Oil painting showing Saraswati
Saraswati is the goddess of knowledge and the arts in Hinduism.

In Buddhism, knowledge that leads to liberation is called vijjā. It contrasts with avijjā or ignorance, which is understood as the root of all suffering. This is often explained in relation to the claim that humans suffer because they crave things that are impermanent. The ignorance of the impermanent nature of things is seen as the factor responsible for this craving.[191] The central goal of Buddhist practice is to stop suffering. This aim is to be achieved by understanding and practicing the teaching known as the Four Noble Truths and thereby overcoming ignorance.[192] Knowledge plays a key role in the classical path of Hinduism known as j?āna yoga or "path of knowledge". It aims to achieve oneness with the divine by fostering an understanding of the self and its relation to Brahman or ultimate reality.[193]

Anthropology

The anthropology of knowledge is a multi-disciplinary field of inquiry.[194] It studies how knowledge is acquired, stored, retrieved, and communicated.[195] Special interest is given to how knowledge is reproduced and changes in relation to social and cultural circumstances.[196] In this context, the term knowledge is used in a very broad sense, roughly equivalent to terms like understanding and culture.[197] This means that the forms and reproduction of understanding are studied irrespective of their truth value. In epistemology, by contrast, knowledge is usually restricted to forms of true belief. The main focus in anthropology is on empirical observations of how people ascribe truth values to meaning contents, like when affirming an assertion, even if these contents are false.[196] This also includes practical components: knowledge is what is employed when interpreting and acting on the world and involves diverse phenomena, such as feelings, embodied skills, information, and concepts. It is used to understand and anticipate events to prepare and react accordingly.[198]

The reproduction of knowledge and its changes often happen through some form of communication used to transfer knowledge.[199] This includes face-to-face discussions and online communications as well as seminars and rituals. An important role in this context falls to institutions, like university departments or scientific journals in the academic context.[196] Anthropologists of knowledge understand traditions as knowledge that has been reproduced within a society or geographic region over several generations. They are interested in how this reproduction is affected by external influences. For example, societies tend to interpret knowledge claims found in other societies and incorporate them in a modified form.[200]

Within a society, people belonging to the same social group usually understand things and organize knowledge in similar ways to one another. In this regard, social identities play a significant role: people who associate themselves with similar identities, like age-influenced, professional, religious, and ethnic identities, tend to embody similar forms of knowledge. Such identities concern both how a person sees themselves, for example, in terms of the ideals they pursue, as well as how other people see them, such as the expectations they have toward the person.[201]

Sociology

The sociology of knowledge is the subfield of sociology that studies how thought and society are related to each other.[202] Like the anthropology of knowledge, it understands "knowledge" in a wide sense that encompasses philosophical and political ideas, religious and ideological doctrines, folklore, law, and technology. The sociology of knowledge studies in what sociohistorical circumstances knowledge arises, what consequences it has, and on what existential conditions it depends. The examined conditions include physical, demographic, economic, and sociocultural factors. For instance, philosopher Karl Marx claimed that the dominant ideology in a society is a product of and changes with the underlying socioeconomic conditions.[202] Another example is found in forms of decolonial scholarship that claim that colonial powers are responsible for the hegemony of Western knowledge systems. They seek a decolonization of knowledge to undermine this hegemony.[203] A related issue concerns the link between knowledge and power, in particular, the extent to which knowledge is power. The philosopher Michel Foucault explored this issue and examined how knowledge and the institutions responsible for it control people through what he termed biopower by shaping societal norms, values, and regulatory mechanisms in fields like psychiatry, medicine, and the penal system.[204]

A central subfield is the sociology of scientific knowledge, which investigates the social factors involved in the production and validation of scientific knowledge. This encompasses examining the impact of the distribution of resources and rewards on the scientific process, which leads some areas of research to flourish while others languish. Further topics focus on selection processes, such as how academic journals decide whether to publish an article and how academic institutions recruit researchers, and the general values and norms characteristic of the scientific profession.[205]

Others

Formal epistemology studies knowledge using formal tools found in mathematics and logic.[206] An important issue in this field concerns the epistemic principles of knowledge. These are rules governing how knowledge and related states behave and in what relations they stand to each other. The transparency principle, also referred to as the luminosity of knowledge, states that it is impossible for someone to know something without knowing that they know it.[p][207] According to the conjunction principle, if a person has justified beliefs in two separate propositions, then they are also justified in believing the conjunction of these two propositions. In this regard, if Bob has a justified belief that dogs are animals and another justified belief that cats are animals, then he is justified to believe the conjunction that both dogs and cats are animals. Other commonly discussed principles are the closure principle and the evidence transfer principle.[208]

Knowledge management is the process of creating, gathering, storing, and sharing knowledge. It involves the management of information assets that can take the form of documents, databases, policies, and procedures. It is of particular interest in the field of business and organizational development, as it directly impacts decision-making and strategic planning. Knowledge management efforts are often employed to increase operational efficiency in attempts to gain a competitive advantage.[209] Key processes in the field of knowledge management are knowledge creation, knowledge storage, knowledge sharing, and knowledge application. Knowledge creation is the first step and involves the production of new information. Knowledge storage can happen through media like books, audio recordings, film, and digital databases. Secure storage facilitates knowledge sharing, which involves the transmission of information from one person to another. For the knowledge to be beneficial, it has to be put into practice, meaning that its insights should be used to either improve existing practices or implement new ones.[210]

Knowledge representation is the process of storing organized information, which may happen using various forms of media and also includes information stored in the mind.[211] It plays a key role in the artificial intelligence, where the term is used for the field of inquiry that studies how computer systems can efficiently represent information. This field investigates how different data structures and interpretative procedures can be combined to achieve this goal and which formal languages can be used to express knowledge items. Some efforts in this field are directed at developing general languages and systems that can be employed in a great variety of domains while others focus on an optimized representation method within one specific domain. Knowledge representation is closely linked to automatic reasoning because the purpose of knowledge representation formalisms is usually to construct a knowledge base from which inferences are drawn.[212] Influential knowledge base formalisms include logic-based systems, rule-based systems, semantic networks, and frames. Logic-based systems rely on formal languages employed in logic to represent knowledge. They use linguistic devices like individual terms, predicates, and quantifiers. For rule-based systems, each unit of information is expressed using a conditional production rule of the form "if A then B". Semantic nets model knowledge as a graph consisting of vertices to represent facts or concepts and edges to represent the relations between them. Frames provide complex taxonomies to group items into classes, subclasses, and instances.[213]

Pedagogy is the study of teaching methods or the art of teaching.[q] It explores how learning takes place and which techniques teachers may employ to transmit knowledge to students and improve their learning experience while keeping them motivated.[215] There is a great variety of teaching methods and the most effective approach often depends on factors like the subject matter and the age and proficiency level of the learner.[216] In teacher-centered education, the teacher acts as the authority figure imparting information and directing the learning process. Student-centered approaches give a more active role to students with the teacher acting as a coach to facilitate the process.[217] Further methodological considerations encompass the difference between group work and individual learning and the use of instructional media and other forms of educational technology.[218]

See also

References

Notes

  1. ^ In this context, testimony is what other people report, both in spoken and written form.
  2. ^ A similar approach was already discussed in Ancient Greek philosophy in Plato's dialogue Theaetetus, where Socrates pondered the distinction between knowledge and true belief but rejected this definition.[22]
  3. ^ Truth is usually associated with objectivity. This view is rejected by relativism about truth, which argues that what is true depends on one's perspective.[24]
  4. ^ A defeater of a belief is evidence that this belief is false.[37]
  5. ^ This view is supported by philosophers such as Peter Unger, who uses this idea as an argument for skepticism.[40]
  6. ^ A distinction similar to the one between knowledge-that and knowledge-how was already discussed in ancient Greece as the contrast between epistēmē (unchanging theoretical knowledge) and technē (expert technical knowledge).[44]
  7. ^ For instance, to know whether Ben is rich can be understood as knowing that Ben is rich, in case he is, and knowing that Ben is not rich, in case he is not.[50]
  8. ^ However, it is controversial to what extent goal-directed behavior in lower animals is comparable to human knowledge-how.[57]
  9. ^ Individuals may lack a deeper understanding of their character and feelings and attaining self-knowledge is one step in psychoanalysis.[73]
  10. ^ Confabulation is a special type of memory error that consists remembering events that did not happen, often provoked by an attempt to fill memory gaps.[95]
  11. ^ An often-cited paradox from the field of formal epistemology is Fitch's paradox of knowability, which states that knowledge has limits because denying this claim leads to the absurd conclusion that every truth is known.[105]
  12. ^ A similar often-cited thought experiment assumes that a person is not a regular human being but a brain in a vat that receives electrical stimuli. These stimuli give the brain the false impression of having a body and interacting with the external world. Since the person is unable to tell the difference, it is argued that they do not know that they have a body responsible for reliable perceptions.[112]
  13. ^ It is controversial to what extent there is a single scientific method that applies equally to all sciences rather than a group of related approaches.[148]
  14. ^ It is controversial how radical the difference between paradigms is and whether they truly are incommensurable.[158]
  15. ^ The internet also reduced the cost of accessing knowledge with a lot of information being freely available.[179]
  16. ^ This principle implies that if Heike knows that today is Monday, then she also knows that she knows that today is Monday.
  17. ^ The exact definition of the term is disputed.[214]

Citations

  1. ^
  2. ^
  3. ^
  4. ^
  5. ^
  6. ^
  7. ^
  8. ^
  9. ^
  10. ^
  11. ^ Steup & Neta 2020, § 2. What Is Knowledge?
  12. ^ Allen 2005
  13. ^
  14. ^
  15. ^
  16. ^
  17. ^ Ichikawa & Steup 2018, § 7. Is Knowledge Analyzable?
  18. ^
  19. ^
  20. ^
  21. ^
  22. ^
  23. ^
  24. ^
  25. ^
  26. ^
  27. ^
  28. ^
  29. ^
    • Ichikawa & Steup 2018, § 1.3 The Justification Condition, § 6.1 Reliabilist Theories of Knowledge
    • Klein 1998, § 4. Foundationalism and Coherentism, § 6. Externalism
    • Hetherington 2022a, § 5a. The Justified-True-Belief Conception of Knowledge, § 7. Knowing’s Point
  30. ^ Hetherington 2022, Lead Section, § Introduction
  31. ^
  32. ^
  33. ^ Ichikawa & Steup 2018, § 3. The Gettier Problem, § 10.2 Fake Barn Cases
  34. ^ Ichikawa & Steup 2018, § 3. The Gettier Problem, § 4. No False Lemmas, § 5. Modal Conditions, § 6. Doing Without Justification?
  35. ^ Steup & Neta 2020, § 2.3 Knowing Facts
  36. ^
  37. ^ McCain, Stapleford & Steup 2021, p. 111
  38. ^
  39. ^
  40. ^ Unger, 1971 & pp198–200
  41. ^
  42. ^
  43. ^
  44. ^ Allen 2005, Lead Section
  45. ^
  46. ^
  47. ^
  48. ^ Hetherington 2022a, § 1b. Knowledge-That, § 1c. Knowledge-Wh
  49. ^
  50. ^ Hetherington 2022a, § 1c. Knowledge-Wh
  51. ^
  52. ^ Woolfolk & Margetts 2012, p. 251
  53. ^ a b Pritchard 2013, 1 Some preliminaries
  54. ^
  55. ^
  56. ^
  57. ^ Pavese 2022, § 7.4 Knowledge-How in Preverbal Children and Nonhuman Animals.
  58. ^
  59. ^
  60. ^
  61. ^
  62. ^
  63. ^ Baehr 2022, Lead Section
  64. ^
  65. ^ Moser 2016, Lead Section
  66. ^
    • Baehr 2022, § 1. An Initial Characterization, § 4. The Relevant Sense of 'Experience'
    • Russell 2020, § 4.1 A Priori Justification Is Justification That Is Independent of Experience
  67. ^
  68. ^
  69. ^
  70. ^ Baehr 2022, § 1. An Initial Characterization, § 6. Positive Characterizations of the A Priori
  71. ^
  72. ^
  73. ^
  74. ^
  75. ^
  76. ^ Schneider & McGrew 2022, pp. 115–116
  77. ^
  78. ^ a b
  79. ^ Barnett 2006, pp. 146–147
  80. ^ Hunter 2009, pp. 151–153
  81. ^
  82. ^
  83. ^
  84. ^
  85. ^
  86. ^
  87. ^
  88. ^
  89. ^
  90. ^ Steup & Neta 2020, § 5.2 Introspection
  91. ^
  92. ^
  93. ^
  94. ^ Steup & Neta 2020, § 5.3 Memory
  95. ^
  96. ^
  97. ^
  98. ^
  99. ^
  100. ^
  101. ^ Rescher 2009, p. 6
  102. ^
  103. ^
  104. ^
  105. ^ Weisberg 2021, § 4.2 The Knowability Paradox (a.k.a. the Church-Fitch Paradox)
  106. ^ Kreeft & Tacelli 2009, p. 371
  107. ^
  108. ^
  109. ^
  110. ^ Yanofsky 2013, pp. 161–164
  111. ^
  112. ^ a b Steup & Neta 2020, § 6.1 General Skepticism and Selective Skepticism
  113. ^
  114. ^ Stroll 2023, § Skepticism
  115. ^
  116. ^
  117. ^
  118. ^
  119. ^
  120. ^
  121. ^
  122. ^ a b c
  123. ^
  124. ^
  125. ^
  126. ^
  127. ^ a b
  128. ^
  129. ^ Klein 1998, § 4. Foundationalism and Coherentism
  130. ^
  131. ^ Pritchard 2013, 2 The value of knowledge
  132. ^
  133. ^
  134. ^
  135. ^
  136. ^ Olsson 2011, p. 875
  137. ^ Pritchard, Turri & Carter 2022, Lead Section, § 6. Other Accounts of the Value of Knowledge
  138. ^
  139. ^ Pritchard, Turri & Carter 2022, § 2. Reliabilism and the Meno Problem, § 3. Virtue Epistemology and the Value Problem
  140. ^ Turri, Alfano & Greco 2021
  141. ^ Pritchard, Turri & Carter 2022, § 2. Reliabilism and the Meno Problem
  142. ^
  143. ^
  144. ^
  145. ^ Degenhardt 2019, pp. 1–6
  146. ^ a b
  147. ^ Moser 2005, p. 386
  148. ^ Hepburn & Andersen 2021, Lead Section, § 1. Overview and organizing themes
  149. ^
  150. ^
  151. ^
  152. ^
  153. ^
  154. ^
  155. ^
  156. ^
  157. ^
  158. ^ Bird 2022, § 6.2 Incommensurability
  159. ^ Plantinga 2018, pp. 222–223
  160. ^
  161. ^
    • Burke 2015, 1. Knowledges and Their Histories: § History and Its Neighbours, 3. Processes: § Four Stages, 3. Processes: § Oral Transmission
    • Doren 1992, pp. xvi–xviii
    • Daston 2017, pp. 142–143
    • Mulsow 2018, p. 159
  162. ^
  163. ^
  164. ^
  165. ^
  166. ^
  167. ^
  168. ^ Trefil 2012, pp. 49–51
  169. ^ Aqil, Babekri & Nadmi 2020, p. 156
  170. ^ Cosman & Jones 2009, p. 148
  171. ^ Gilliot 2018, p. 81
  172. ^
  173. ^ Power 1970, pp. 243–244
  174. ^
  175. ^
  176. ^
  177. ^
  178. ^
  179. ^ Danesi 2013, pp. 178–181
  180. ^ Clark 2022, Lead Section, § 2. The Evidentialist Objection to Belief in God
  181. ^ a b Penelhum 1971, 1. Faith, Scepticism and Philosophy
  182. ^
  183. ^
    • Clark 2022, Lead Section, § 2. The Evidentialist Objection to Belief in God
    • Forrest 2021, Lead Section, § 2. The Rejection of Enlightenment Evidentialism
    • Dougherty 2014, pp. 97–98
  184. ^
    • Clark 2022, § 2. The Evidentialist Objection to Belief in God
    • Forrest 2021, Lead Section, 2. The Rejection of Enlightenment Evidentialism
  185. ^ Clark 2022, § 2. The Evidentialist Objection to Belief in God
  186. ^ Stevenson 2003, pp. 72–73
  187. ^
  188. ^
  189. ^
  190. ^
  191. ^
  192. ^
  193. ^
  194. ^
  195. ^ Cohen 2010, pp. S193–S202
  196. ^ a b c Allwood 2013, pp. 69–72
  197. ^
  198. ^ Barth 2002, pp. 1–2
  199. ^
  200. ^
  201. ^
  202. ^ a b
  203. ^
  204. ^
  205. ^
  206. ^ Weisberg 2021
  207. ^
  208. ^ Klein 1998, § 7. Epistemic Principles
  209. ^
  210. ^
  211. ^
  212. ^
  213. ^
  214. ^ Watkins & Mortimore 1999, pp. 1–3
  215. ^
  216. ^
  217. ^ Emaliana 2017, pp. 59–61
  218. ^

Sources

什么食物对眼睛好 痰多吃什么好 beginning什么意思 鸡痘用什么药效果好 笔仙是什么
女孩第一次来月经需要注意什么 屡禁不止的意思是什么 花甲和什么不能一起吃 401什么意思 拍拖什么意思
咪咪头疼是什么原因 榴莲壳有什么作用 未曾谋面什么意思 骨骼闭合了还有什么办法可以长高 甜醋是什么醋
梨状肌综合症吃什么药 丁克什么意思 经常干咳是什么原因 频繁打哈欠是什么原因 董小姐是什么意思
蚊虫叮咬用什么药膏hcv9jop6ns1r.cn 辣椒炒肉用什么肉hcv8jop5ns4r.cn 孙悟空的原名叫什么hcv9jop4ns9r.cn 什么人适合吃西洋参dajiketang.com 舌尖起泡是什么原因hcv7jop7ns0r.cn
冰箱什么品牌好clwhiglsz.com 胸口不舒服是什么原因hcv8jop3ns3r.cn 雌激素分泌过多是什么原因引起的hcv8jop0ns3r.cn 金瓜是什么瓜hcv8jop0ns6r.cn 32岁属什么的生肖hcv9jop3ns2r.cn
总是困是什么原因hcv7jop6ns2r.cn 云指什么生肖hcv8jop2ns7r.cn 人言轻微是什么意思hcv8jop6ns3r.cn 示字旁与什么有关hcv8jop9ns0r.cn 时光荏苒是什么意思hcv8jop6ns3r.cn
阴道发臭是什么原因hcv8jop9ns5r.cn r医学是什么意思adwl56.com 肉桂粉是什么做的hcv9jop1ns3r.cn 心脏由什么组织构成hcv8jop7ns0r.cn 梦到父母离婚是什么意思aiwuzhiyu.com
百度