肌肤甲错是什么意思| 嗯呢什么意思| 喉咙痛有黄痰吃什么药| 送老师什么花好| dce是什么溶剂| 农历六月是什么星座| sc1是什么意思| 喝酒前吃什么不会醉| 下午五点半是什么时辰| 小清新是什么意思啊| 生龙活虎是什么意思| 特仑苏是什么意思| 双字五行属什么| 测尿酸挂什么科| 2000年属什么的| 过奖了是什么意思| 老打嗝是什么病的前兆| 谷氨酰胺是什么| 八月生日什么星座| kb什么意思| 什么叫肾病综合征| 摩拳擦掌是什么生肖| 天亮是什么时辰| 女人吃桑葚有什么好处| 腰封是什么意思| 检查肺结节挂什么科| plt是什么| 艾滋病有什么症状| 塌方是什么意思| 柿子与什么食物相克| 热鸡蛋滚脸有什么作用| 为什么头皮会疼| 心花怒放是什么生肖| 减肥不能吃什么水果| 办慢性病有什么好处| 耳朵里发炎用什么药好| 过氧化氢是什么| 梦见流水是什么征兆| 痛风挂什么科室| 化验痰可以检查出什么| 医保和社保有什么区别| 睡着了流口水是什么原因| 什么时机塞给医生红包| 衣冠禽兽指什么生肖| 什么情况会染上鼠疫| 女人腰疼是什么妇科病| 头晕眼花吃什么药| 下身瘙痒用什么药| 456什么意思| 尿多吃什么药| 黄褐斑是什么样的图片| 什么是适度水解奶粉| 微创手术是什么| 美味佳肴是什么意思| 不吃肉对身体有什么影响| 安琪儿是什么意思| 小猫的胡须有什么作用| 日光性皮炎用什么药| 肝内钙化斑是什么意思| 黄芪不适合什么人吃| 宜祭祀是什么意思| 贻笑大方是什么意思| 降血糖吃什么菜| 大便很细是什么原因| 眼睛干涩有异物感用什么眼药水| 吃什么升白细胞| 压迫感是什么意思| 张家界莓茶有什么功效| 贪污是什么意思| 区域经理的岗位职责是什么| 肾病钾高吃什么食物好| 为什么月经每个月提前| 另煎兑服是什么意思| 脚腿肿是什么原因引起的| 助听器什么牌子最好| 水果皇后是什么水果| 针灸后需要注意什么| 什么时候满月| 压迫是什么意思| 糜烂性胃炎吃什么药效果好| 冬字五行属什么| 后人是什么意思| 孩子高烧不退是什么原因| 复方板蓝根和板蓝根有什么区别| 天女散花是什么意思| 小辣椒是什么意思| 肾囊肿用什么药| 糖尿病有什么症状| 热锅凉油是什么意思| 经常手麻是什么原因| 跑步机cal是什么意思| 农历7月20日是什么星座| epa是什么| 什么照片看不出照的是谁| 西葫芦炒什么好吃| 脆皖鱼是什么鱼| 信访局是干什么的| 聚乙二醇是什么| 筋是什么组织| 虾青素有什么作用| 马和驴为什么能杂交| 人言可畏什么意思| 蛀牙是什么原因引起的| 检查妇科清洁度三是什么意思| 萎靡是什么意思| 十一月是什么星座| 脖子左侧疼是什么原因| 晚上七点半是什么时辰| 野生刺猬吃什么| 去医院看膝盖挂什么科| 牙齿松动吃什么药| 什么球不能踢脑筋急转弯| 亦金读什么| 数字7的风水含义是什么| fl是什么| 造口是什么意思| 偷窥是什么意思| 长春都有什么大学| 吃榴莲有什么坏处| 滞纳金是什么意思| 晚上九点多是什么时辰| 皮肤癣用什么药最好| 视什么如什么| 微博会员有什么功能| 月经量少吃什么好| pg是什么单位| 阳光明媚下一句接什么| 喉结下面是什么部位| 指甲紫色是什么病的征兆| 什么清肠茶好| 胆囊是干什么用的| 狗为什么喜欢吃屎| 农历9月21日是什么星座| 木鱼花是什么做的| 毛峰茶属于什么茶| 羊蝎子是什么肉| 为什么一抽烟就想拉屎| 什么古迹| 奕字属于五行属什么| 市辖区是什么意思| 什么是聚酯纤维| 一什么手套| 龙年是什么年| 女孩生日送什么| 急性肠胃炎吃什么药效果好| 榴莲不能和什么水果一起吃| 吃什么可以快速减肥| 装修属于什么行业| npc是什么意思| 神态是什么意思| 春饼卷什么菜好吃| 吃了什么药不能喝酒| tpa是什么意思| 小麦粉可以做什么| 六月什么星座| 艺考是什么| 黑天鹅是什么意思| 医师是什么级别| 14年是什么年| 芯字五行属什么| 勺子是什么意思| 吃桑葚对身体有什么好处| 吃什么可以降火| 胃窦是什么| 六月初二是什么日子| 喝牛奶放屁多是什么原因| 羊蛋是什么部位| 小什么名字好听| 瑾字属于五行属什么| 脱髓鞘疾病是什么病| 不甚是什么意思| 男人左眼跳是什么意思| 什么上什么下| 头好出汗是什么原因| 心电图逆钟向转位是什么意思| 跑业务是什么工作| 石敢当是什么神仙| 拿的起放的下是什么意思| 妇科千金片和三金片有什么区别| 肝血管瘤是什么原因引起的| 狐臭应该挂什么科| 乙状结肠炎吃什么药| 胸腔积液是什么原因引起的| 产后为什么脸部松弛| 如饥似渴是什么意思| 起鸡皮疙瘩是什么原因| 鼻涕带血是什么原因引起的| 为什么警察叫条子| 林黛玉是个什么样的人| 什么叫二婚线| 闰6月是什么意思| 陈五行属什么| 士官是什么级别| 肉蔻是什么样子| 猫腻是什么意思| 北肖指什么生肖| 梅毒为什么会自愈| 蚊子最喜欢什么血型| 里脊肉炒什么好吃| 包皮有什么影响| 双手发麻是什么原因| 大什么大| 6月12日是什么日子| 卵巢早衰吃什么药调理最好| 山川载不动太多悲哀是什么歌| 黑眼圈是什么原因| 乳腺低回声是什么意思| 补钾用什么药| 胸闷气短是什么症状| 印度属于什么亚| 什么时候恢复高考| 女大四岁有什么说法| 榴莲为什么臭| 存脐带血有什么用| 心律不齐什么症状| 蛇吃什么东西| 排卵期和排卵日有什么区别| 巴子是什么意思| 哈密瓜为什么叫哈密瓜| 男生为什么会晨勃| 梁下放床有什么禁忌| 作茧自缚是什么意思| 稀饭配什么菜好吃| 香港商务签证需要什么条件| 坐骨神经吃什么药| 有小肚子是什么原因| 2001年属什么生肖| 溺爱的意思是什么| 连长相当于地方什么官| 纾字五行属什么| 喉咙长溃疡是什么原因| 吴亦凡为什么叫牛| 冰心的原名是什么| gold什么意思| 尿道炎吃什么消炎药| 台湾什么时候回归的| 七月有什么节| 按摩是什么意思| 吃绝户是什么意思| 猪胰子是什么东西| 低密度脂蛋白胆固醇偏低是什么意思| 大逆不道什么意思| 绿树成荫是什么季节| m 是什么单位| 英国全称叫什么| 草莽是什么意思| 早餐吃什么比较好| 中央电视台台长什么级别| 阴道里面有个肉球是什么| 阴茎硬不起吃什么药| 总流鼻血是什么原因| 三伏天是什么| 桑葚搭配什么泡水喝最好| 什么是性侵| 化疗后吃什么药| 梦见男朋友出轨了是什么意思| 大马猴是什么意思| 受是什么意思| 什么是宫腔镜检查| 降火祛痘喝什么茶| au是什么意思| od什么意思| 属猪的本命佛是什么佛| 脂肪肝用什么药| 百度Jump to content

牛肉和什么炒最好吃

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
(Redirected from Deleuze)
百度 这一刻,天梭表展台前的她,沉浸于品牌的时光长廊,与品牌享有同质的精神世界。

Gilles Deleuze
Born18 January 1925
Paris, France
Died4 November 1995(2025-08-05) (aged 70)
Paris, France
Education
EducationUniversity of Paris
(BA, MA, DrE)
Academic advisors
Philosophical work
Era20th-century philosophy
RegionWestern philosophy
School
InstitutionsUniversity of Paris VIII
Notable students
Main interests
Notable ideas

Gilles Louis René Deleuze[a] (18 January 1925 – 4 November 1995) was a French philosopher who, from the early 1950s until his death in 1995, wrote on philosophy, literature, film, and fine art. His most popular works were the two volumes of Capitalism and Schizophrenia: Anti-Oedipus (1972) and A Thousand Plateaus (1980), both co-written with psychoanalyst Félix Guattari. His metaphysical treatise Difference and Repetition (1968) is considered to be his magnum opus.[2][b][c]

An important part of Deleuze's oeuvre is devoted to the reading of other philosophers: the Stoics, Leibniz, Hume, Kant, Nietzsche, Spinoza, and Bergson. A. W. Moore, citing Bernard Williams's criteria for a great thinker, ranks Deleuze among the "greatest philosophers".[4] Although he once characterized himself as a "pure metaphysician",[5] his work has influenced a variety of disciplines across the humanities, including philosophy, art, and literary theory, as well as movements such as post-structuralism and postmodernism.[6]

Life

[edit]

Early life

[edit]

Gilles Deleuze was born into a middle-class family in Paris and lived there for most of his life. His mother was Odette Camaüer and his father, Louis, was an engineer.[7] His initial schooling was undertaken during World War II, during which time he attended the Lycée Carnot. He also spent a year in khagne at the Lycée Henri IV. During the Nazi occupation of France, Deleuze's brother, three years his senior, Georges, was arrested for his participation in the French Resistance, and died while in transit to a concentration camp.[8] In 1944, Deleuze went to study at the Sorbonne. His teachers there included several noted specialists in the history of philosophy, such as Georges Canguilhem, Jean Hyppolite, Ferdinand Alquié, and Maurice de Gandillac. Deleuze's lifelong interest in the canonical figures of modern philosophy owed much to these teachers.

Career

[edit]

Deleuze passed the agrégation in philosophy in 1948, and taught at various lycées (Amiens, Orléans, Louis le Grand) until 1957, when he took up a position at the University of Paris. In 1953, he published his first monograph, Empiricism and Subjectivity, on David Hume. This monograph was based on his 1947 DES (dipl?me d'études supérieures [fr]) thesis,[9] roughly equivalent to an M.A. thesis, which was conducted under the direction of Jean Hyppolite and Georges Canguilhem.[10] From 1960 to 1964, he held a research fellow position at the Centre National de Recherche Scientifique. During this time he published the seminal Nietzsche and Philosophy (1962) and befriended Michel Foucault. From 1964 to 1969, he was a professor at the University of Lyon. In 1968, Deleuze defended his two DrE dissertations amid the ongoing May 68 demonstrations; he later published his two dissertations under the titles Difference and Repetition (supervised by Gandillac) and Expressionism in Philosophy: Spinoza (supervised by Alquié).

In 1969, he was appointed to the University of Paris VIII, an experimental school organized to implement educational reform.[11] This new university drew a number of well-known academics, including Foucault (who suggested Deleuze's hiring) and the psychoanalyst Félix Guattari. Deleuze taught at Paris VIII until his retirement in 1987.

Personal life

[edit]

Deleuze's outlook on life was sympathetic to transcendental ideas, "nature as god" ethics, and the monist experience. Some of the important ideas he advocated for and found inspiration in include his personally coined expression pluralism = monism, as well as the concepts of Being and Univocity.

He married Denise Paul "Fanny" Grandjouan in 1956 and they had two children.

According to James Miller, Deleuze portrayed little visible interest in actually doing many of the risky things he so vividly conjured up[clarification needed] in his lectures and writing. Married, with two children, he outwardly lived the life of a conventional French professor. He kept his fingernails untrimmed because, as he once explained, he lacked "normal protective fingerprints", and therefore could not "touch an object, particularly a piece of cloth, with the pads of my fingers without sharp pain".[12]

When once asked to talk about his life, he replied: "Academics' lives are seldom interesting."[13] Deleuze concludes his reply to this critic thus:

What do you know about me, given that I believe in secrecy? ... If I stick where I am, if I don't travel around, like anyone else I make my inner journeys that I can only measure by my emotions, and express very obliquely and circuitously in what I write. ... Arguments from one's own privileged experience are bad and reactionary arguments.[14]

Death

[edit]

Deleuze, who had suffered from respiratory ailments from a young age,[15] developed tuberculosis in 1968 and underwent lung removal.[16] He suffered increasingly severe respiratory symptoms for the rest of his life.[17][18] In the last years of his life, simple tasks such as writing required laborious effort. Overwhelmed by his respiratory problems, he died by suicide on 4 November 1995,[19] throwing himself from the window of his apartment.[20]

Before his death, Deleuze had announced his intention to write a book entitled La Grandeur de Marx (The Greatness of Marx), and left behind two chapters of an unfinished project entitled Ensembles and Multiplicities (these chapters have been published as the essays "Immanence: A Life" and "The Actual and the Virtual").[21] He is buried in the cemetery of the village of Saint-Léonard-de-Noblat.[22]

Philosophy

[edit]

Deleuze's works fall into two groups: on the one hand, monographs interpreting the work of other philosophers (Baruch Spinoza, Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, David Hume, Immanuel Kant, Friedrich Nietzsche, Henri Bergson, Michel Foucault) and artists (Marcel Proust, Franz Kafka, Francis Bacon); on the other, eclectic philosophical tomes organized by concept (e.g., difference, sense, event, economy, cinema, desire, philosophy). However, both of these aspects are seen by his critics and analysts as often overlapping, in particular, due to his prose and the unique mapping of his books that allow for multifaceted readings.

Metaphysics

[edit]

Deleuze's main philosophical project in the works he wrote prior to his collaborations with Guattari can be summarized as an inversion of the traditional metaphysical relationship between identity and difference. Traditionally, difference is seen as derivative from identity: e.g., to say that "X is different from Y" assumes some X and Y with at least relatively stable identities (as in Plato's forms). On the contrary, Deleuze claims that all identities are effects of difference. Identities are neither logically nor metaphysically prior to difference, Deleuze argues, "given that there exist differences of nature between things of the same genus."[23] That is, not only are no two things ever the same, the categories used to identify individuals in the first place derive from differences. Apparent identities such as "X" are composed of endless series of differences, where "X" = "the difference between x and x", and "x" = "the difference between...", and so forth. Difference, in other words, goes all the way down. To confront reality honestly, Deleuze argues, beings must be grasped exactly as they are, and concepts of identity (forms, categories, resemblances, unities of apperception, predicates, etc.) fail to attain what he calls "difference in itself." "If philosophy has a positive and direct relation to things, it is only insofar as philosophy claims to grasp the thing itself, according to what it is, in its difference from everything it is not, in other words, in its internal difference."[24]

Like Kant, Deleuze considers traditional notions of space and time as unifying forms imposed by the subject. He, therefore, concludes that pure difference is non-spatiotemporal; it is an idea, what Deleuze calls "the virtual". (The coinage refers to Proust's definition of what is constant in both the past and the present: "real without being actual, ideal without being abstract.")[25] While Deleuze's virtual ideas superficially resemble Plato's forms and Kant's ideas of pure reason, they are not originals or models, nor do they transcend possible experience; instead they are the conditions of actual experience, the internal difference in itself. "The concept they [the conditions] form is identical to its object."[26] A Deleuzean idea or concept of difference is therefore not a wraith-like abstraction of an experienced thing, it is a real system of differential relations that creates actual spaces, times, and sensations.[27]

Thus, Deleuze at times refers to his philosophy as a transcendental empiricism (empirisme transcendantal), alluding to Kant.[28][29] In Kant's transcendental idealism, experience only makes sense when organized by intuitions (namely, space and time) and concepts (such as causality). Assuming the content of these intuitions and concepts to be qualities of the world as it exists independently of human perceptual access, according to Kant, spawns seductive but senseless metaphysical beliefs (for example, extending the concept of causality beyond possible experience results in unverifiable speculation about a first cause). Deleuze inverts the Kantian arrangement: experience exceeds human concepts by presenting novelty, and this raw experience of difference actualizes an idea, unfettered by prior categories, forcing the invention of new ways of thinking (see Epistemology).

Simultaneously, Deleuze claims that being is univocal, i.e., that all of its senses are affirmed in one voice. Deleuze borrows the doctrine of ontological univocity from the medieval philosopher John Duns Scotus. In medieval disputes over the nature of God, many eminent theologians and philosophers (such as Thomas Aquinas) held that when one says that "God is good", God's goodness is only analogous to human goodness. Scotus argued to the contrary that when one says that "God is good", the goodness in question is exactly the same sort of goodness that is meant when one says "Jane is good". That is, God only differs from humans in degree, and properties such as goodness, power, reason, and so forth are univocally applied, regardless of whether one is talking about God, a person, or a flea.

Deleuze adapts the doctrine of univocity to claim that being is, univocally, difference. "With univocity, however, it is not the differences which are and must be: it is being which is Difference, in the sense that it is said of difference. Moreover, it is not we who are univocal in a Being which is not; it is we and our individuality which remains equivocal in and for a univocal Being."[30] Here Deleuze at once echoes and inverts Spinoza, who maintained that everything that exists is a modification of the one substance, God or Nature. For Deleuze, there is no one substance, only an always-differentiating process, an origami cosmos, always folding, unfolding, refolding. Deleuze summarizes this ontology in the paradoxical formula "pluralism = monism".[31]

Difference and Repetition (1968) is Deleuze's most sustained and systematic attempt to work out the details of such a metaphysics, but his other works develop similar ideas. In Nietzsche and Philosophy (1962), for example, reality is a play of forces; in Anti-Oedipus (1972), a "body without organs"; in What is Philosophy? (1991), a "plane of immanence" or "chaosmos".

Epistemology

[edit]

Deleuze's unusual metaphysics entails an equally atypical epistemology, or what he calls a transformation of "the image of thought". According to Deleuze, the traditional image of thought, found in philosophers such as Aristotle, René Descartes, and Edmund Husserl, misconceives thinking as a mostly unproblematic business. Truth may be hard to discover—it may require a life of pure theorizing, or rigorous computation, or systematic doubt—but thinking is able, at least in principle, to correctly grasp facts, forms, ideas, etc. It may be practically impossible to attain a God's-eye, neutral point of view, but that is the ideal to approximate: a disinterested pursuit that results in a determinate, fixed truth; an orderly extension of common sense. Deleuze rejects this view as papering over the metaphysical flux, instead claiming that genuine thinking is a violent confrontation with reality, an involuntary rupture of established categories. Truth changes thought; it alters what people think is possible. By setting aside the assumption that thinking has a natural ability to recognize the truth, Deleuze says, people attain a "thought without image", a thought always determined by problems rather than solving them. "All this, however, presupposes codes or axioms which do not result by chance, but which do not have an intrinsic rationality either. It's just like theology: everything about it is quite rational if you accept sin, the immaculate conception, and the incarnation. Reason is always a region carved out of the irrational—not sheltered from the irrational at all, but traversed by it and only defined by a particular kind of relationship among irrational factors. Underneath all reason lies delirium, and drift."[32]

The Logic of Sense, published in 1969, is one of Deleuze's most peculiar works in the field of epistemology. Michel Foucault, in his essay "Theatrum Philosophicum" about the book, attributed this to how he begins with his metaphysics but approaches it through language and truth; the book is focused on "the simple condition that instead of denouncing metaphysics as the neglect of being, we force it to speak of extrabeing".[33] In it, he refers to epistemological paradoxes: in the first series, as he analyzes Lewis Carroll's Alice in Wonderland, he remarks that "the personal self requires God and the world in general. But when substantives and adjectives begin to dissolve, when the names of pause and rest are carried away by the verbs of pure becoming and slide into the language of events, all identity disappears from the self, the world, and God."[34]

Deleuze's peculiar readings of the history of philosophy stem from this unusual epistemological perspective. To read a philosopher is no longer to aim at finding a single, correct interpretation, but is instead to present a philosopher's attempt to grapple with the problematic nature of reality. "Philosophers introduce new concepts, they explain them, but they don't tell us, not completely anyway, the problems to which those concepts are a response. [...] The history of philosophy, rather than repeating what a philosopher says, has to say what he must have taken for granted, what he didn't say but is nonetheless present in what he did say."[35]

Likewise, rather than seeing philosophy as a timeless pursuit of truth, reason, or universals, Deleuze defines philosophy as the creation of concepts. For Deleuze, concepts are not identity conditions or propositions, but metaphysical constructions that define a range of thinking, such as Plato's ideas, Descartes's cogito, or Kant's doctrine of the faculties. A philosophical concept "posits itself and its object at the same time as it is created."[36] In Deleuze's view, then, philosophy more closely resembles practical or artistic production than it does an adjunct to a definitive scientific description of a pre-existing world (as in the tradition of John Locke or Willard Van Orman Quine).

In his later work (from roughly 1981 onward), Deleuze sharply distinguishes art, philosophy, and science as three distinct disciplines, each relating to reality in different ways. While philosophy creates concepts, the arts create novel qualitative combinations of sensation and feeling (what Deleuze calls "percepts" and "affects"), and the sciences create quantitative theories based on fixed points of reference such as the speed of light or absolute zero (which Deleuze calls "functives"). According to Deleuze, none of these disciplines enjoy primacy over the others:[37] they are different ways of organizing the metaphysical flux, "separate melodic lines in constant interplay with one another."[38] For example, Deleuze does not treat cinema as an art representing an external reality, but as an ontological practice that creates different ways of organizing movement and time.[39] Philosophy, science, and art are equally, and essentially, creative and practical. Hence, instead of asking traditional questions of identity such as "is it true?" or "what is it?", Deleuze proposes that inquiries should be functional or practical: "what does it do?" or "how does it work?"[40]

Values

[edit]

In ethics and politics Deleuze again echoes Spinoza, albeit in a sharply Nietzschean key. Following his rejection of any metaphysics based on identity, Deleuze criticizes the notion of an individual as an arresting or halting of differentiation (as the etymology of the word "individual" suggests[clarification needed]). Guided by the naturalistic ethics of Spinoza and Nietzsche, Deleuze instead seeks to understand individuals and their moralities as products of the organization of pre-individual desires and powers.[41]

In the two volumes of Capitalism and Schizophrenia, Anti-Oedipus (1972) and A Thousand Plateaus (1980), Deleuze and Guattari describe history as a congealing and regimentation of "desiring-production" (a concept combining features of Freudian drives and Marxist labor) into the modern individual (typically neurotic and repressed), the nation-state (a society of continuous control), and capitalism (an anarchy domesticated into infantilizing commodification). Deleuze, following Karl Marx, welcomes capitalism's destruction of traditional social hierarchies as liberating but inveighs against its homogenization of all values to the aims of the market.

The first part of Capitalism and Schizophrenia undertakes a universal history and posits the existence of a separate socius (the social body that takes credit for production) for each mode of production: the earth for the tribe, the body of the despot for the empire, and capital for capitalism."[42][43]

In his 1990 essay "Postscript on the Societies of Control" ("Post-scriptum sur les sociétés de contr?le"), Deleuze builds on Foucault's notion of the society of discipline to argue that society is undergoing a shift in structure and control. Where societies of discipline were characterized by discrete physical enclosures (such as schools, factories, prisons, office buildings, etc.), institutions and technologies introduced since World War II have dissolved the boundaries between these enclosures. As a result, social coercion and discipline have moved into the lives of individuals considered as "masses, samples, data, markets, or 'banks'." The mechanisms of modern societies of control are described as continuous, following and tracking individuals throughout their existence via transaction records, mobile location tracking, and other personally identifiable information.[44]

But how does Deleuze square his pessimistic diagnoses with his ethical naturalism? Deleuze claims that standards of value are internal or immanent: to live well is to fully express one's power, to go to the limits of one's potential, rather than to judge what exists by non-empirical, transcendent standards. Modern society still suppresses difference and alienates people from what they can do. To affirm reality, which is a flux of change and difference, established identities must be overturned and so become all that they can become—though exactly what cannot be known in advance. The pinnacle of Deleuzean practice, then, is creativity. "Herein, perhaps, lies the secret: to bring into existence and not to judge. If it is so disgusting to judge, it is not because everything is of equal value, but on the contrary, because what has value can be made or distinguished only by defying judgment. What expert judgment, in art, could ever bear on the work to come?"[45]

Deleuze's interpretations

[edit]

Deleuze's studies of individual philosophers and artists are purposely heterodox. Deleuze once famously described his method of interpreting philosophers as "buggery (enculage)", as sneaking behind an author and producing an offspring which is recognizably his, yet also monstrous and different.[46]

The various monographs thus are not attempts to present what Nietzsche or Spinoza strictly intended, but re-stagings of their ideas in different and unexpected ways. Deleuze's peculiar readings aim to enact the creativity he believes is the acme of philosophical practice.[47] A parallel in painting Deleuze points to is Francis Bacon's Study after Velázquez—it is quite beside the point to say that Bacon "gets Velasquez wrong".[48] Similar considerations apply, in Deleuze's view, to his own uses of mathematical and scientific terms, pace critics such as Alan Sokal: "I'm not saying that Resnais and Prigogine, or Godard and Thom, are doing the same thing. I'm pointing out, rather, that there are remarkable similarities between scientific creators of functions and cinematic creators of images. And the same goes for philosophical concepts, since there are distinct concepts of these spaces."[49]

Similarities with Heidegger

[edit]

From the 1930s onward, German philosopher Martin Heidegger wrote in a series of manuscripts and books on concepts of Difference, Identity, Representation, and Event; notably among these the Beitr?ge zur Philosophie (Vom Ereignis) (Written 1936-38; published posthumously 1989); none of the relevant texts were translated into French by Deleuze's death in 1995, excluding any strong possibility of appropriation. However, Heidegger's early work can be traced through mathematician Albert Lautman, who drew heavily from Heidegger's Sein und Zeit and Vom Wesen des Grundes (1928), which James Bahoh describes as having "...decisive influence on the twentieth century mathematician and philosopher [...] whose theory of dialectical Ideas Deleuze appropriated and modified for his own use."[50] The similarities between Heidegger's later, post-turn, 1930-1976 thought and Deleuze's early works in the 60s and 70s are generally described by Deleuze-scholar Daniel W. Smith in the following way:

"Difference and Repetition could be read as a response to Being and Time (for Deleuze, Being is difference, and time is repetition)."[51]

Bahoh continues in saying that: "...then Beitr?ge could be read as Difference and Repetition's unknowing and anachronistic doppelg?nger."[52] Deleuze and Heidegger's philosophy is considered to converge on the topics of Difference and the Event. Where, for Heidegger, an evental being is constituted in part by difference as "...an essential dimension of the concept of event"; for Deleuze, being is difference, and difference "differentiates by way of events." In contrast to this, however, Jussi Backman argues that, for Heidegger, being is united only insofar as it consists of and is difference, or rather as the movement of difference, not too dissimilar to Deleuze's later claims:

"...the unity and univocity of being (in the sense of being), its 'selfsameness,' paradoxically consists exclusively in difference."[53]

This mutual apprehension of a differential, Evental ontology lead both thinkers into an extended critique of the representation characteristic to Platonic, Aristotelian, and Cartesian thought; as Joe Hughes states: "Difference and Repetition is a detective novel. It tells the story of what some readers of Deleuze might consider a horrendous crime [...]: the birth of representation."[54] Heidegger formed his critiques most decisively in the concept of the fourfold [German: das Geviert], a non-metaphysical grounding for the thing (as opposed to "object") as "ungrounded, mediated, meaningful, and shared"[55] united in an "event of appropriation" [Ereignis]. This evental ontology continues in Identit?t und Differenz, where the fundamental concept expressed in Difference and Repetition, of dethroning the primacy of identity, can be seen throughout the text. Even in earlier Heideggerian texts such as Sein und Zeit, however, the critique of representation is "...cast in terms of the being of truth, or the processes of uncovering and covering (grounded in Dasein's existence) whereby beings come into and withdraw from phenomenal presence." In parallel, Deleuze's extended critique of representation (in the sense of detailing a "genealogy" of the antiquated beliefs as well) is given "...in terms of being or becoming as difference and repetition, together with genetic processes of individuation whereby beings come to exist and pass out of existence."[56]

Time and space, for both thinkers, is also constituted in nearly identical ways. Time-space in the Beitr?ge and the three syntheses in Difference and Repetition[57] both apprehend time as grounded in difference, whilst the distinction between the time-space of the world [Welt] and the time-space as the eventual production of such a time-space is mirrored by Deleuze's categorization between the temporality of what is actual and temporality of the virtual in the first and the second/third syntheses respectively.

Another parallel can be found in their utilization of so-called "generative paradoxes," or rather problems whose fundamental problematic element is constantly outside the categorical grasp fond of formal, natural, and human sciences. For Heidegger, this is the Earth in the fourfold, something which has as one of its traits the behaviour of "resisting articulation," what he characterizes as a "strife";[58] for Deleuze, a similar example can be spotted in the paradox of regress, or of indefinite proliferation in the Logic of Sense.[59]

Reception

[edit]

In the 1960s, Deleuze's portrayal of Nietzsche as a metaphysician of difference rather than a reactionary mystic contributed greatly to the plausibility and popularity of "left-wing Nietzscheanism" as an intellectual stance.[60] His books Difference and Repetition (1968) and The Logic of Sense (1969) led Michel Foucault to declare that "one day, perhaps, this century will be called Deleuzian."[61] (Deleuze, for his part, said Foucault's comment was "a joke meant to make people who like us laugh, and make everyone else livid."[62]) In the 1970s, the Anti-Oedipus, written in a style by turns vulgar and esoteric,[63] offering a sweeping analysis of the family, language, capitalism, and history via eclectic borrowings from primarily Marx, Freud, Lacan, and Nietzsche, but also featuring insights from dozens of other writers, was received as a theoretical embodiment of the anarchic spirit of May 1968. In 1994 and 1995, L'Abécédaire de Gilles Deleuze, an eight-hour series of interviews between Deleuze and Claire Parnet, aired on France's Arte Channel.[64]

In the 1980s and 1990s, almost all of Deleuze's books were translated into English. Deleuze's work is frequently cited in English-speaking academia (in 2007, e.g., he was the 11th most frequently cited author in English-speaking publications in the humanities, between Freud and Kant).[65] In the English-speaking academy, Deleuze's work is typically classified as continental philosophy.[66]

However, some French and some Anglophone philosophers criticised Deleuze's work.

According to Pascal Engel, Deleuze's metaphilosophical approach makes it impossible to reasonably disagree with a philosophical system, and so destroys meaning, truth, and philosophy itself. Engel summarizes Deleuze's metaphilosophy thus: "When faced with a beautiful philosophical concept you should just sit back and admire it. You should not question it."[67]

American philosopher Stanley Rosen objects to Deleuze's interpretation of Nietzsche's eternal return.[68]

Vincent Descombes argues that Deleuze's account of a difference that is not derived from identity (in Nietzsche and Philosophy) is incoherent.[69]

Slavoj ?i?ek states that the Deleuze of Anti-Oedipus ("arguably Deleuze's worst book"),[70] the "political" Deleuze under the "'bad' influence" of Guattari, ends up, despite protestations to the contrary, as "the ideologist of late capitalism".[71]

Allegations of idealism and negligence of material conditions

[edit]

Peter Hallward argues that Deleuze's insistence that being is necessarily creative and always-differentiating entails that his philosophy can offer no insight into, and is supremely indifferent to, the material conditions of existence. Thus Hallward claims that Deleuze's thought is literally other-worldly, aiming only at a passive contemplation of the dissolution of all identity into the theophanic self-creation of nature.[72]

Descombes argues that his analysis of history in Anti-Oedipus is 'utter idealism', criticizing reality for falling short of a non-existent ideal of schizophrenic becoming.[69]

?i?ek claims that Deleuze's ontology oscillates between materialism and idealism.[73]

Relation with monism

[edit]

Alain Badiou claims that Deleuze's metaphysics only apparently embraces plurality and diversity, remaining at bottom monist. Badiou further argues that, in practical matters, Deleuze's monism entails an ascetic, aristocratic fatalism akin to ancient Stoicism.[74]

American philosopher Todd May argues that Deleuze's claim that difference is ontologically primary ultimately contradicts his embrace of immanence, i.e., his monism. However, May believes that Deleuze can discard the primacy-of-difference thesis, and accept a Wittgensteinian holism without significantly altering his practical philosophy.[75]

It has more recently been argued by the Swedish philosopher Rafael Holmberg [d] that Deleuze's criticism of the history of philosophy as the metaphysical priority of identity over difference is a false distinction, and that Deleuze inadvertently reaches conclusions akin to such idealist philosophers of identity as Schelling.[76]

Subjectivity and individuality

[edit]

Other European philosophers have criticized Deleuze's theory of subjectivity. For example, Manfred Frank claims that Deleuze's theory of individuation as a process of bottomless differentiation fails to explain the unity of consciousness.[77]

?i?ek also calls Deleuze to task for allegedly reducing the subject to "just another" substance and thereby failing to grasp the nothingness that, according to Lacan and ?i?ek, defines subjectivity. What remains worthwhile in Deleuze's oeuvre, ?i?ek finds, are precisely Deleuze's engagements with virtuality as the product of negativity.[78]

Science wars

[edit]

In Fashionable Nonsense (1997), physicists Alan Sokal and Jean Bricmont accuse Deleuze of abusing mathematical and scientific terms, particularly by sliding between accepted technical meanings and his own idiosyncratic use of those terms in his works. Sokal and Bricmont state that they don't object to metaphorical reasoning, including with mathematical concepts, but mathematical and scientific terms are useful only insofar as they are precise. They give examples of mathematical concepts being "abused" by taking them out of their intended meaning, rendering the idea into normal language reduces it to truism or nonsense. In their opinion, Deleuze used mathematical concepts about which the typical reader might be not knowledgeable, and thus served to display erudition rather than enlightening the reader. Sokal and Bricmont state that they only deal with the "abuse" of mathematical and scientific concepts and explicitly suspend judgment about Deleuze's wider contributions.[79]

Influence

[edit]

Other scholars in continental philosophy, feminist studies and sexuality studies have taken Deleuze's analysis of the sexual dynamics of sadism and masochism with a level of uncritical celebration following the 1989 Zone Books translation of the 1967 booklet on Leopold von Sacher-Masoch, Le froid et le cruel (Coldness and Cruelty). As sexuality historian Alison M. Moore notes, Deleuze's own value placed on difference is poorly reflected in this booklet which fails to differentiate between Masoch's own view of his desire and that imposed upon him by the pathologizing forms of psychiatric thought prevailing in the late nineteenth century which produced the concept of 'masochism' (a term Masoch himself emphatically rejected).[80]

Smith, Protevi and Voss note "Sokal and Bricmont’s 1999 intimations" underestimated Deleuze's awareness of mathematics and pointed out several "positive views of Deleuze’s use of mathematics as provocations for [...] his philosophical concepts", and that Deleuze's epistemology and ontology can be "brought together" with dynamical systems theory, chaos theory, biology, and geography.[2]

Bibliography

[edit]
Single-authored
Original French English Translation
Empirisme et subjectivité (1953) Empiricism and Subjectivity (1991)
Nietzsche et la philosophie (1962) Nietzsche and Philosophy (1983)
La philosophie critique de Kant (1963) Kant's Critical Philosophy (1983)
Proust et les signes

(1964, 3rd exp. ed. 1976)

Proust and Signs

(1973, 2nd exp. ed. 2000)

Nietzsche (1965) Pure Immanence (2001)
Le Bergsonisme (1966) Bergsonism (1988)
Présentation de Sacher-Masoch (1967) Masochism: Coldness and Cruelty (1989)
Différence et répétition (1968) Difference and Repetition (1994)
Spinoza et le problème de l'expression

(Paris: éditions de Minuit, 1968 & 1985)

Expressionism in Philosophy: Spinoza (1990)
Logique du sens (1969) The Logic of Sense (1990)
Dialogues

(1977, 2nd exp. ed. 1996, with Claire Parnet)

Dialogues II

(1987, 2nd exp. ed. 2002)

One Less Manifesto (1978) In Superpositions (with Carmelo Bene)
Spinoza – Philosophie pratique, 2nd ed.

(Paris: éditions de Minuit, 1981)

Spinoza: Practical Philosophy (1988)
Francis Bacon – Logique de la sensation (1981) Francis Bacon: The Logic of Sensation (2003)
Cinéma I: L'image-mouvement (1983) Cinema 1: The Movement-Image (1986)
Cinéma II: L'image-temps (1985) Cinema 2: The Time-Image (1989)
Foucault (1986) Foucault (1988)
Le pli – Leibniz et le baroque (1988) The Fold: Leibniz and the Baroque (1993)
Périclès et Verdi: La philosophie de Francois Chatelet (1988) In Dialogues II, revised ed. (2007)
Pourparlers (1990) Negotiations (1995).
Critique et clinique (1993) Essays Critical and Clinical (1997)
L'?le déserte et autres textes (2002) Desert Islands and Other Texts 1953–1974 (2003)
Deux régimes de fous et autres textes (2004) Two Regimes of Madness: Texts and Interviews 1975–1995 (2006)

In collaboration with Félix Guattari

In collaboration with Michel Foucault

  • "Intellectuals and Power: A Discussion Between Gilles Deleuze and Michel Foucault". Telos 16 (Summer 1973). New York: Telos Press (reprinted in L'?le déserte et autres textes / Desert Islands and Other Texts; see above)

Documentaries

[edit]

See also

[edit]

Notes

[edit]
  1. ^ /d??lu?z/ d?-LOOZ; French: [?il d?l?z]
  2. ^ "Difference and Repetition is definitely the most important work published by Deleuze." (Edouard Morot-Sir, from the back cover of the first edition of the English translation)
  3. ^ James Williams: "It is nothing less than a revolution in philosophy and stands out as one of the great philosophical works of the twentieth century" (James Williams, Gilles Deleuze's Difference and Repetition: A Critical Introduction and Guide [Edinburgh UP, 2003], p. 1).

References

[edit]
  1. ^ Horner, Robyn (2005). Jean-Luc Marion: a Theo-Logical Introduction. Burlington: Ashgate. p. 3.
  2. ^ a b c Smith, Daniel W.; Protevi, John; Voss, Daniela. "Gilles Deleuze". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 17 February 2011.
  3. ^ Simon Choat, Marx Through Post-Structuralism: Lyotard, Derrida, Foucault, Deleuze, Continuum, 2010, ch. 5.
  4. ^ A. W. Moore, The Evolution of Modern Metaphysics: Making Sense of Things, Cambridge University Press, 2012, p. 543: 'intellectual power and depth; a grasp of the sciences; a sense of the political, and of human destructiveness as well as creativity; a broad range and a fertile imagination; an unwillingness to settle for the superficially reassuring; and, in an unusually lucky case, the gifts of a great writer.'
  5. ^ Beaulieu, Alain; Kazarian, Edward; Sushytska, Julia (eds.): Gilles Deleuze and Metaphysics. (Lanham, MD: Lexington Books, 2014)
  6. ^ See, for example, Steven Best and Douglas Kellner, Postmodern Theory (Guilford Press, 1991), which devotes a chapter to Deleuze and Guattari.
  7. ^ Beckman, Frida (2017). Gilles Deleuze: Critical Lives. Reaktion Books. p. 15. ISBN 9781780237770.
  8. ^ Fran?ois Dosse, Gilles Deleuze and Felix Guattari: Intersecting Lives, trans. Deborah Glassman (New York: Columbia University Press, 2010), p. 89.
  9. ^ Alan D. Schrift (2006), Twentieth-Century French Philosophy: Key Themes and Thinkers, Blackwell Publishing, p. 117.
  10. ^ Daniela Voss, Conditions of Thought: Deleuze and Transcendental Ideas, Edinburgh University Press, 2013, p. 76.
  11. ^ "Gilles Deleuze". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 16 February 2025.
  12. ^ James Miller, The Passion of Michel Foucault, New York: Harper Collins, 1993, p. 196.
  13. ^ Negotiations, p. 137.
  14. ^ Negotiations, pp. 11–12.
  15. ^ Fran?ois Dosse, Deleuze and Guattari: Intersecting Lives, trans D. Glassman, CUP 2010, p. 98.
  16. ^ Fran?ois Dosse, Deleuze and Guattari: Intersecting Lives, trans D. Glassman, CUP 2010, p. 178.
  17. ^ Bolzinger, Jean-Michel (26 December 2003). "Gilles Deleuze et les médecins". Association Médicale Mosellane de Perfectionnement Post Universitaire. Archived from the original on 5 May 2019. Retrieved 4 October 2006.
  18. ^ "Gilles Deleuze et les médecins". Archived from the original on 5 May 2019. Retrieved 4 October 2006.
  19. ^ "Gilles Deleuze". Encyclop?dia Britannica. Retrieved 8 July 2009.
  20. ^ "French Philosopher Gilles Deleuze Commits Suicide at 70". AP NEWS. Retrieved 15 April 2021.
  21. ^ Fran?ois Dosse, Gilles Deleuze and Felix Guattari: Intersecting Lives, pp. 454–455. "Immanence: A Life" has been translated and published in Pure Immanence and Two Regimes of Madness, while "The Actual and Virtual" has been translated and published as an appendix to the second edition of Dialogues.
  22. ^ "Communauté de Communes de Noblat" (PDF). Archived from the original (PDF) on 18 October 2014.
  23. ^ "Bergson's Conception of Difference", in Desert Islands, p. 33.
  24. ^ Desert Islands, p. 32.
  25. ^ Proust, Le Temps Retrouvé, ch. III.
  26. ^ Desert Islands, p. 36.
  27. ^ See "The Method of Dramatization" in Desert Islands, and "Actual and Virtual" in Dialogues II.
  28. ^ Gilles Deleuze, Difference and Repetition, Continuum, 2004[1968], pp. 56 and 143.
  29. ^ Adrian Parr (ed.), The Deleuze Dictionary (Revised Edition), Edinburgh University Press, 2010, p. 289: "Unlike Kant, Deleuze does not conceive of [...] unthought conditions as abstract or necessary philosophical entities, but as contingent tendencies beyond the reach of empirical consciousness."
  30. ^ Difference and Repetition, p. 39.
  31. ^ A Thousand Plateaus, p. 20.
  32. ^ Desert Islands, p. 262.
  33. ^ "Theatrum Philosophicum". www.generation-online.org.
  34. ^ The Logic of Sense, p. 3.
  35. ^ Negotiations, p. 136.
  36. ^ What Is Philosophy?, p. 22.
  37. ^ Negotiations, p. 123.
  38. ^ Negotiations, p. 125.
  39. ^ Cinema 1: The Movement Image
  40. ^ Negotiations, p. 21: "We're strict functionalists: what we're interested in is how something works".
  41. ^ Laurie, Timothy; Stark, Hannah (2017), "Love's Lessons: Intimacy, Pedagogy and Political Community", Angelaki: Journal of the Theoretical Humanities, 22 (4): 69–79
  42. ^ "Gilles Deleuze". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 1 July 2018.).
  43. ^ Daniel W. Smith, Henry Somers-Hall (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Deleuze, Cambridge University Press, 2012, p. 137.
  44. ^ Deleuze, Gilles (October 1992). "Postscript on the Societies of Control". October. 59: 3–7. JSTOR 778828.
  45. ^ Essays Critical and Clinical, p. 135.
  46. ^ Negotiations, p. 6. See also: Daniel W. Smith, "The Inverse Side of the Structure: Zizek on Deleuze on Lacan", Criticism (2004): "Deleuze's all-too-well-known image of philosophical "buggery," which makes thinkers produce their own "monstrous" children"; Robert Sinnerbrink (in "Nomadology or Ideology? Zizek’s Critique of Deleuze", Parrhesia 1 (2006): 62–87) describes the "popular topic" of Deleuze's "notorious remarks"; Donald Callen (in "The Difficult Middle", Rhizomes 10 (Spring 2005)) describes "intellectual buggery" as "what Deleuze himself famously said about his encounters with the works of other philosophers." Deleuze's buggery analogy is also cited by, among many others, Brian Massumi, A User's Guide to Capitalism and Schizophrenia (MIT Press, 1992), p. 2; Slavoj ?i?ek, Organs without Bodies (Routledge, 2004), p. 48; Ian Buchanan, A Deleuzian Century? (Duke UP, 1999), p. 8; Jean-Jacques Lecercle, Deleuze and Language (Macmillan, 2002), p. 37; Gregg Lambert, The Non-Philosophy of Gilles Deleuze (Continuum, 2002), p. x; Claire Colebrook, Understanding Deleuze (Allen & Unwin, 2003), p. 73; and Charles Stivale, Gilles Deleuze: Key Concepts (McGill-Queen's, 2005), p. 3.
  47. ^ Desert Islands, p. 144.
  48. ^ Francis Bacon: The Logic of Sensation, pp. 46f: "[Bacon] let loose ... presences" already in Velázquez's painting. Cf. the passage cited above, from Negotiations, p. 136: "The history of philosophy, rather than repeating what a philosopher says, has to say what he must have taken for granted, what he didn't say but is nonetheless present in what he did say."
  49. ^ Negotiations, pp. 124–125.
  50. ^ Bahoh, James (2016). Heidegger and Deleuze: The Groundwork of Evental Ontology. Duquesne University. p. 3.
  51. ^ Smith, Daniel (2012). Essays on Deleuze. Edinburgh University Press. p. 30. ISBN 978-0-7486-4334-9. OCLC 1302164289.
  52. ^ Bahoh, James (2016). Heidegger and Deleuze: The Groundwork of Evental Ontology. Duquesne University. pp. 6–7.
  53. ^ Backman, Jussi (2015). Complicated Presence: Heidegger and the Postmetaphysical Unity of Being. SUNY Press. p. 234. ISBN 978-1-4384-5648-5. OCLC 946567759.
  54. ^ Hughes, Joe (2009). Deleuze's Difference and Repetition. London: Continuum. p. 24. ISBN 978-0-8264-2112-8.
  55. ^ Mitchell, Andrew (2015). The Fourfold: Reading the Late Heidegger. Northwestern University. p. 308. ISBN 978-0-8101-3076-0.
  56. ^ Bahoh, James (2016). Heidegger and Deleuze: The Groundwork of Evental Ontology. Duquesne University. p. 113.
  57. ^ Deleuze, Gilles (2001). Difference and Repetition. London: Continuum. p. 79. ISBN 0-8264-5957-9.
  58. ^ Canan, Alberto Carillo (2001), Tymieniecka, Anna-Teresa (ed.), "The Concept of "Earth" in Heidegger: History and the "Oblivion of Being"", Passions of the Earth in Human Existence, Creativity, and Literature, Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands, pp. 101–110, doi:10.1007/978-94-010-0930-0_8, ISBN 978-94-010-0930-0, retrieved 3 May 2022
  59. ^ Deleuze, Gilles (1990). Logic of Sense. London: The Athlone Press. p. 28. ISBN 1-4742-3488-7. OCLC 920869689.
  60. ^ See, e.g., the approving reference to Deleuze's Nietzsche study in Jacques Derrida's essay "Différance", or Pierre Klossowski's monograph Nietzsche and the Vicious Circle, dedicated to Deleuze. More generally, see D. Allison (ed.), The New Nietzsche (MIT Press, 1985), and L. Ferry and A. Renaut (eds.), Why We Are Not Nietzscheans (University of Chicago Press, 1997).
  61. ^ Foucault, "Theatrum Philosophicum", Critique 282, p. 885.
  62. ^ Negotiations, p. 4. However, in a later interview, Deleuze commented: "I don't know what Foucault meant, I never asked him" (Negotiations, p. 88).
  63. ^ Sometimes in the same sentence: "one is thus traversed, broken, fucked by the socius" (Anti-Oedipus, p. 347).
  64. ^ "Charles J. Stivale -- A-F Summary of L'Abecedaire de Gilles Deleuze". www.langlab.wayne.edu. 6 December 2021.
  65. ^ "The most cited authors of books in the humanities". timeshighereducation.co.uk. 26 March 2009. Retrieved 4 July 2010.
  66. ^ See, e.g., Simon Glendinning, The Idea of Continental Philosophy (Edinburgh University Press, 2006), p. 54.
  67. ^ Barry Smith (ed.), European Philosophy and the American Academy, p. 34.
  68. ^ Rosen, Stanley (1995). The Mask of Enlightenment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. ix–x. ISBN 0-521-49546-6.
  69. ^ a b Descombes, Vincent (1998). Modern French Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. 155–6, 175–8. ISBN 0-521-29672-2.
  70. ^ ?i?ek 2004, p. 21
  71. ^ ?i?ek 2004, pp. 32, 20, and 184.
  72. ^ Hallward, Peter (2006). Out of This World. New York: Verso. ISBN 978-1844675555.
  73. ^ Slavoj ?i?ek, Organs without Bodies, 2004, pp. 19–32, esp. p. 21: "Is this opposition not, yet again, that of materialism versus idealism? In Deleuze, this means The Logic of Sense versus Anti-Oedipus." See also p. 28 for "Deleuze's oscillation between the two models" of becoming.
  74. ^ Badiou, Alain (2000). Deleuze: the clamor of being. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota. ISBN 0-8166-3139-5.
  75. ^ May, Todd (1 July 1997). Reconsidering Difference: Nancy, Derrida, Levinas, and Deleuze. Pennsylvania State Univ Pr. ISBN 978-0-271-01657-3.
  76. ^ Holmberg, Rafael (2022). "The Indifference of Objectivity to Difference and Identity: The Paradox of Subject-Object Obfuscation Between Schelling and Deleuze". Cosmos and History: The Journal of Natural and Social Philosophy. 18 (2): 112–128.
  77. ^ Frank, Manfred (1989). What Is Neostructuralism?. University of Minnesota Press. p. 385. ISBN 978-0816616022.
  78. ^ ?i?ek 2004, p. 68: "This brings us to the topic of the subject that, according to Lacan, emerges in the interstice of the 'minimal difference,' in the minimal gap between two signifiers. In this sense, the subject is 'a nothingness, a void, which exists.' ... This, then, is what Deleuze seems to get wrong in his reduction of the subject to (just another) substance. Far from belonging to the level of actualization, of distinct entities in the order of constituted reality, the dimension of the 'subject' designates the reemergence of the virtual within the order of actuality. 'Subject' names the unique space of the explosion of virtuality within constituted reality."
  79. ^ Alan Sokal; Jean Bricmont (29 October 1999). Fashionable Nonsense: Postmodern Intellectuals' Abuse of Science. St Martins Press (ny). pp. 22–25, 154–169. ISBN 978-0-312-20407-5.
  80. ^ Alison Moore, Recovering Difference in the Deleuzian Dichotomy of Masochism-without-Sadism, Angelaki volume 14, issue 3
[edit]
chris是什么意思 口加大是什么字 眉中间有竖纹代表什么 匪夷所思是什么意思 印度人属于什么人种
吃什么降肌酐 双儿是什么意思 什么叫静息心率 什么是矿物质 检查乳腺挂什么科
一什么种子 a代表什么 属狗的什么命 嘱托是什么意思 预防脑梗吃什么药
吃什么能生精和提高精子质量 病例是什么 白头发多吃什么食物能变黑 履历是什么意思 男人更年期在什么年龄
老公的妈妈叫什么cj623037.com 爱心是什么意思hcv8jop0ns9r.cn 什么是恒牙hcv8jop1ns3r.cn 兔死狐悲是什么生肖hcv9jop4ns2r.cn 建档是什么意思hcv9jop6ns1r.cn
杨柳代表什么生肖hcv7jop5ns0r.cn 自刎是什么意思hcv8jop6ns7r.cn 4月26是什么星座creativexi.com 我靠是什么意思hcv7jop9ns3r.cn 1994年什么命hcv8jop5ns0r.cn
肝病初期有什么症状hcv8jop2ns9r.cn 肉便器是什么意思hcv9jop3ns6r.cn 病人出院送什么花luyiluode.com 合肥原名叫什么名字hcv8jop9ns2r.cn 毁三观是什么意思啊hcv9jop7ns5r.cn
接吻会传染什么病hcv8jop7ns3r.cn 降血脂吃什么药hcv9jop1ns3r.cn 对峙什么意思xjhesheng.com 上海有什么好玩的地方旅游景点hcv7jop5ns1r.cn 吃什么能提高免疫力hcv8jop9ns2r.cn
百度