吃炒黑豆有什么好处和坏处| 火奥念什么| 补阳气吃什么药| 初三什么时候毕业| 女人胯骨疼是什么原因| 脚麻木是什么原因| 肝低密度灶是什么意思| 木耳菜不能和什么一起吃| 文胸是什么意思| 屏幕总成带框和不带框有什么区别| 晚上看到黄鼠狼什么预兆| 口腔溃疡吃什么好的快| 共振是什么意思| 什么时候普及高中义务教育| 心脏看什么科室| 早茶是什么意思| 稻谷什么时候成熟| 什么雷声| 财神爷叫什么名字| 木鱼花是什么| 9月出生的是什么星座| 燕窝是什么东西做的| 十一月三十是什么星座| 候和侯有什么区别| 汗疱疹是什么原因引起| 6月12日什么星座| 肠胀气吃什么药| 经常手麻是什么原因| 呼吸困难是什么原因引起的| 梦到鸡是什么意思| 头皮屑多用什么洗发水效果好| 谷草转氨酶偏低是什么原因| 胰岛素高有什么危害| 奶水不足吃什么下奶最快| viki什么意思| 老夫老妻什么意思| 嗓子吞咽疼痛吃什么药| 寄什么快递最便宜| 1983年出生是什么命| 头发干燥是什么原因| 布拉吉是什么| 迷糊是什么意思| 自我为中心是什么意思| 白天不咳嗽晚上咳嗽吃什么药| 闰六月有什么讲究| 为什么这样对我| 眼睛干涩用什么药水| 面试是什么意思| 龋病是什么意思| 冬枣是什么季节的水果| 权志龙为什么叫gd| 慢性结肠炎吃什么药| 检查是否怀孕要做什么检查| 什么的去路| cdf1是什么意思| 1211是什么星座| 百叶是什么| 十月份出生的是什么星座| 脾胃湿热吃什么中成药| 拉稀是什么原因| 1996年是属什么生肖| 快乐大本营为什么停播| 天天晚上睡觉做梦是什么原因| 月子早餐吃什么好| 为什么飞机撞鸟会坠机| suv什么意思| 黄体不足吃什么补最快| 大脚趾头麻木是什么原因| 破伤风什么症状| 鱼蛋是什么| 什么样的西瓜甜| 怀孕后期脚肿是什么原因| 11月25日是什么星座| 乌鸡白凤丸适合什么人吃| 左眼皮肿是什么原因引起的| 8五行属什么| 经理是什么级别| 小猫的特点是什么| 什么药治便秘效果最好最快| 裸官是什么意思| ca125是什么检查项目| 标准员是干什么的| 久负盛名的负是什么意思| 高尿酸有什么症状| 玉竹有什么功效| 直肠ca代表什么病| 大三阳是什么意思| 胃间质瘤为什么不建议切除| 每天吃鸡蛋有什么好处和坏处| 肌层回声不均匀是什么意思| 周瑜和诸葛亮是什么关系| 双子座什么性格| 血压偏低是什么原因造成的| 手指头脱皮是什么原因| 打饱嗝是什么原因造成的| 鳞状上皮内低度病变是什么意思| 梦见古墓是什么意思| 右边脑袋疼是什么原因| 两眼中间的位置叫什么| 什么狗不掉毛适合家养| 什么牌助听器好| 六月初二是什么日子| 什么颜色加什么颜色等于紫色| 北上广深是什么意思| 专场是什么意思| 属蛇适合佩戴什么饰品| 个体差异是什么意思| 非主流什么意思| 耄耋什么意思| 血小板压积偏低是什么原因| 丁克夫妻是什么意思| 肾寒吃什么中成药| 喝什么茶可以减肥| 岁月蹉跎什么意思| 没腿毛的男人代表什么| 梦见很多蛇是什么意思| 绅士是什么意思| 1968年什么时候退休| 和南圣众是什么意思| 锶是什么意思| 男性婚检都检查什么项目| 白斑有什么症状图片| 贫血喝什么茶| 拔牙后吃什么消炎药最好| 唐氏综合征是什么原因造成的| 樱桃不能和什么一起吃| 为什么会有黑眼圈| 床上什么虫子夜间咬人| 脚崴了用什么药| 左眼皮跳是什么预兆呢| 什么锅好| 栀子泡水喝有什么好处| 气道高反应是什么意思| 护照需要什么材料| 舌头上有溃疡是什么原因| 菠萝和什么不能一起吃| 滑肠是什么意思| 凉拌菜用什么醋最好| 气管炎吃什么药| 集锦是什么意思| 名存实亡是什么意思| r标是什么意思| 夏天为什么会感冒| 无量寿经讲的是什么| 睡觉做噩梦是什么原因| 正财代表什么| 什么而不什么| 传染病八项包括什么| 恶趣味什么意思| 侍寝是什么意思| 什么是居间费| 睡美人最怕得什么病| 婴儿什么时候会走路| 黄麻是什么| 东山再起是什么生肖| 胃肠外科是看什么病的| 早日康复是什么意思| 晚上猫叫有什么预兆| 糟老头是什么意思| 早上起床腰酸痛是什么原因| 刀个刀个刀刀那是什么刀| 什么是升华| 打坐有什么好处| 97年的牛是什么命| 叶黄素什么时间吃最好| 什么原因会导致月经推迟| 女人眉心有痣代表什么| 手上掉皮什么原因| 白天为什么能看到月亮| 地球为什么叫地球| 阳春三月指什么生肖| l代表什么单位| strange是什么意思| 什么情况下做喉镜| 环形红斑是什么病| 降钙素原高是什么原因| 咖啡对身体有什么危害| 骨癌的前兆是什么症状| 男人长期喝什么茶最好| 幽门螺杆菌是什么| 消防大队长是什么级别| 扁平苔藓是什么病| 小腿内侧是什么经络| 爸爸的爸爸叫什么| 小孩睡觉流口水是什么原因| 80分贝相当于什么声音| mlb是什么意思| 人有三急指的是什么| 什么水果泡酒最好| 饭后胃胀吃什么药| 女人腿肿是什么原因引起的| 宫外孕是什么意思| 什么的树林| 寅是什么意思| 梦见吃鸡蛋是什么意思| 长期贫血对身体有什么危害| 吃什么对甲状腺有好处| 6.5号是什么星座| 吃什么能提升血小板| 送对象什么礼物好| 坐月子不能吃什么| jio是什么意思| 梦见跳舞是什么意思| 计算机二级什么时候查成绩| 生长发育科检查些什么| 什么叫早泄| 肚脐叫什么穴位| 鼻子里流出黄水是什么原因| pp是什么意思| 字字珠玑是什么意思| hp医学上是什么意思| 糖尿病患者能吃什么水果| 粉红是什么意思| 缘故的故是什么意思| 舌头边上有锯齿状是什么原因| 戴玉对身体有什么好处| 孕吐吃什么药| 2月25日是什么星座| ube手术是什么意思| 格力空调se是什么意思| 木辛读什么| 吃什么都吐是什么原因| 胡牌是什么意思| 护理主要学什么| 结肠炎不能吃什么食物| review是什么意思| 吃豆腐什么意思| 83岁属什么生肖| 9号来的月经什么时候是排卵期| 心脏做什么检查最准确| 常流鼻血是什么原因| 臆想什么意思| 海鲜不能和什么水果一起吃| 女儿红是什么酒| 政字五行属什么| 画是什么结构| 子宫和宫颈有什么区别| 背部疼痛挂什么科| 脑梗吃什么药可以恢复的快| 孕妇鼻炎犯了可以用什么药治疗| 为什么七星瓢虫是益虫| 痰多吃什么好| 何去何从是什么意思| 碧根果和核桃有什么区别| 肺有问题会出现什么症状| 翡翠属于什么五行| 左甲状腺是什么病| 黄历冲生肖是什么意思| 钠尿肽高是什么原因| 什么是权力| 胃不好吃什么水果| 一穷二白是什么意思| 吃什么头发长得快| cbg是什么意思| 婴儿长牙有什么症状| 侧重点是什么意思| 为什么会眼压高| 人的脾脏起什么作用| 思诺思是什么药| 杭州灵隐寺求什么最灵| gopro是什么意思| 首鼠两端什么意思| 地蛋是什么| 梦到生儿子有什么预兆| 百度Jump to content

【审管】不动产过户“一站式窗口”太不方便了

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
百度 改革涉及的部门要制定完善事中事后监管细则,自本通知发布之日起20个工作日内将适宜公开的向社会公布并加强宣传、确保落实。

Formal semantics is the scientific study of linguistic meaning through formal tools from logic and mathematics. It is an interdisciplinary field, sometimes regarded as a subfield of both linguistics and philosophy of language. Formal semanticists rely on diverse methods to analyze natural language. Many examine the meaning of a sentence by studying the circumstances in which it would be true. They describe these circumstances using abstract mathematical models to represent entities and their features. The principle of compositionality helps them link the meaning of expressions to abstract objects in these models. This principle asserts that the meaning of a compound expression is determined by the meanings of its parts.

Propositional and predicate logic are formal systems used to analyze the semantic structure of sentences. They introduce concepts like singular terms, predicates, quantifiers, and logical connectives to represent the logical form of natural language expressions. Type theory is another approach utilized to describe sentences as nested functions with precisely defined input and output types. Various theoretical frameworks build on these systems. Possible world semantics and situation semantics evaluate truth across different hypothetical scenarios. Dynamic semantics analyzes the meaning of a sentence as the information contribution it makes.

Using these and similar theoretical tools, formal semanticists investigate a wide range of linguistic phenomena. They study quantificational expressions, which indicate the quantity of something, like the sentence "all ravens are black". An influential proposal analyzes them as relations between two sets—the set of ravens and the set of black things in this example. Quantifiers are also used to examine the meaning of definite and indefinite descriptions, which denote specific entities, like the expression "the president of Kenya". Formal semanticists are also interested in tense and aspect, which provide temporal information about events and circumstances. In addition to studying statements about what is true, semantics also investigates other sentences types such as questions and imperatives. Other investigated linguistic phenomena include intensionality, modality, negation, plural expressions, and the influence of contextual factors.

Formal semantics is relevant to various fields. In logic and computer science, formal semantics refers to the analysis of meaning in artificially constructed logical and programming languages. In cognitive science, some researchers rely on the insights of formal semantics to study the nature of the mind. Formal semantics has its roots in the development of modern logic starting in the late 19th century. Richard Montague's work in the late 1960s and early 1970s was pivotal in applying these logical principles to natural language, inspiring many scholars to refine his insights and apply them to diverse linguistic phenomena.

Definition

[edit]

Formal semantics is a branch of linguistics and philosophy that studies linguistic meaning using formal methods. To analyze language in a precise and systematic manner, it incorporates ideas from logic, mathematics, and philosophy of language, like the concepts of truth conditions, model theory, and compositionality.[1] Because of the prominence of these concepts, formal semantics is also referred to as truth-conditional semantics and model-theoretic semantics.[2]

The primary focus of formal semantics is the analysis of natural languages such as English, Sanskrit, Quechua, and American Sign Language.[3] They investigate diverse linguistic phenomena, including reference, quantifiers, plurality, tense, aspect, vagueness, modality, scope, binding, conditionals, questions, and imperatives.[4]

Understood in a wide sense, formal semantics also includes the study of artificial or constructed languages. This covers the formal languages used in the logical analysis of arguments, such as the language of first-order logic, and programming languages in computer science, such as C++, JavaScript, and Python.[5] Formal semantics is related to formal pragmatics since both are subfields of formal linguistics. One key difference is that formal pragmatics centers on how language is used in communication rather than the problem of meaning in general.[6]

Methodology

[edit]

Formal semanticists rely on diverse methods, conceptual tools, and background assumptions, which distinguish the field from other branches of semantics. Most of these principles originate in logic, mathematics, and the philosophy of language.[7] One key principle is that an adequate theory of meaning needs to accurately predict sentences' truth conditions. A sentence's truth conditions are the circumstances under which it would be true. For example, the sentence "Tina is tall and happy" is true if Tina has the property of being tall and also the property of being happy; these are its truth conditions. This principle reflects the idea that understanding a sentence requires knowing how it relates to reality and under which circumstances it would be appropriate to use it.[8]

Formal semanticists test their theories using the linguistic intuitions of competent speakers.[9] A key source of data comes from judgments concerning entailment, a relation between sentences—called premises and conclusions—in which truth is preserved. For instance, the sentence "Tina is tall and happy" entails the sentence "Tina is tall" because the truth of the first sentence guarantees the truth of the second. One aspect of understanding the meaning of a sentence is comprehending what it does and does not entail.[10][a] The study of entailment relations helps formal semanticists build new theories and verify whether existing theories accurately reflect the intuitions of native speakers.[9]

Diagram with arrows from words to symbols of abstract objects
Formal semantics constructs abstract models that map natural language expressions to individual objects and sets of objects.[12]

One major goal of research in formal semantics is to uncover and explain the range of variation across human languages.[13] As part of this typological work, researchers have sought to uncover principles that apply to all languages known as semantic universals. A proposed universal is that languages only allow determiners which have the property of being conservative, indicating that the human language faculty cannot lexicalize many quantifiers that are possible in principle.[14] Crosslinguistic research has also been used to inform theoretical issues within semantics. For example, early research on the semantics of English sparked debate over whether tense markers are quantificational or referential. Subsequent work on Javanese, Atayal, St’át?imcets, and Tlingit has been taken as evidence that natural languages actually make both interpretations available.[15] Similarly, evidence from sign languages has been used to support certain analyses of coreference which are hard to test in spoken languages because the crucial elements are covert.[16] In order to collect data on languages that they themselves do not speak, formal semanticists carry out fieldwork.[17]

Formal semanticists typically analyze language by proposing a system of model theoretic interpretation. In such a system, a sentence is evaluated relative to a mathematical structure called a model that maps each expression to an abstract object.[b] Models rely on set theory and introduce abstract objects for all entities in this situation. For example, a model of a situation where Tina is tall and happy may include an abstract object representing Tina and two sets of objects—one for all tall entities and another for all happy entities. Different models introduce different objects and group them into different sets while interpretation functions link natural language expressions to these objects and sets. Using this approach, semanticists can precisely calculate the truth values of sentences. For example, the sentence "Tina is tall" is true in models where the abstract object corresponding to the name "Tina"[c] is in the set corresponding to the predicate "tall". In this way, model theoretic interpretation makes it possible to formally capture truth conditions and entailments.[20]

Photo of a woman with dark, voluminous hair
Pauline Jacobson suggested direct compositionality as a methodological principle assuming a close link between syntax and semantics.[21]

The principle of compositionality is another key methodological assumption for analyzing the meaning of natural language sentences and linking them to abstract models. It states that the meaning of a compound expression is determined by the meanings of its parts and the way they are combined. According to this principle, if a person knows the meanings of the name "Tina", the verb "is", and the adjective "happy", they can understand the sentence "Tina is happy" even if they have never heard this specific combination of words before. The principle of compositionality explains how language users can comprehend an infinite number of sentences based on their knowledge of a finite number of words and rules.[22]

Semantic formalisms differ in whether they adopt the method of direct interpretation or indirect interpretation. In direct interpretation, the semantic interpretation rules map natural language expressions directly to their denotations, whereas indirect interpretation maps them to expressions of some formal language. For example, in direct interpretation the name "Barack Obama" would be mapped to the man himself, while a system of indirect interpretation would map it to a logical constant "o" which would then be mapped to the man himself. In this way, direct interpretation can be seen as providing a model theory for natural languages themselves, while indirect interpretation provides a system of logic translation and then relies on the model theory of the formal language. These two methods are in principle equivalent, but are often chosen based on practical or expository considerations.[23] To keep their task managable, formal semanticists sometimes limit their studies to particular fragments of whatever language they are studying.[24]

Formal systems and theories

[edit]

Propositional and predicate logic

[edit]
Black-and-white photo of a bronze bust of a bearded man
Gottlob Frege developed predicate logic and used it to analyze natural language arguments.[25]

Formal semanticists often represent truth conditions using propositional or predicate logic. Propositional logic employs letters like and to represent simple statements. These can be combined to form complex formulas using logical connectives such as (and), (or), and (if...then). For example, using the method of indirect interpretation, the sentence "Alice is happy and Bob is rich" can be translated into propositional logic with the formula , where stands for "Alice is happy" and stands for "Bob is rich". Of key interest to semantic analysis is that the truth value of these compound statements is directly determined by the truth values of the simple statements. For instance, the formula is only true if both and are true; otherwise, it is false.[26]

Predicate logic extends propositional logic using symbols for singular terms, predicates, and quantifiers. Singular terms refer to specific entities, whereas predicates represent properties of and relations between entities. For instance, the sentence "Alice is happy" can be translated as the formula , where is a logical constant and is a predicate.[d] Quantifiers express that a certain condition applies to some or all entities. For example, the sentence "Someone is happy" can be represented with the formula , where the existential quantifier indicates that happiness applies at least to one person. Similarly, the idea that everyone is happy can be expressed through the formula , where is the universal quantifier.[28]

There are different ways how natural language sentences can be translated into predicate logic. A common approach interprets verbs as predicates. Intransitive verbs, like "sleeps" and "dances", have a subject but no objects and are interpreted as one-place predicates. Transitive verbs, like "loves" and "gives", have one or more objects and are interpreted as predicates with two or more places. For example, the sentence "Bob loves Alice" can be formalized as , using the two-place predicate . Typically, not every word in natural language sentences has a direct counterpart symbol in the logic translation, and in some cases, the pattern of the logical formula differs significantly from the surface structure of the natural language sentence. For example, sentences like "all cats are animals" are usually translated as (for all entities, if the entity is a cat then the entity is an animal) even though the expression "if...then" () is not present in the original sentence.[29]

Many early approaches to formal semantics, such as the works of Gottlob Frege, Rudolf Carnap, and Donald Davidson, relied primarily on predicate logic.[30]

Lambda calculus

[edit]
Diagram of a parse tree of the sentence "Alice likes Bob" with types
Type-theortic analysis of the sentence "Alice likes Bob". The blue letters indicate the type of the expression. The word "Bob" is first applied to the word "likes", resulting in a function to which the word "Alice" is then applied.[31]

Formal semantics employs the typed lambda calculus to analyze the denotations of parts of sentences. Using the typed lambda calculus, one can formalize the denotation of the sentence "Tina loves Mary" with the formula , just like in predicate logic. However, the lambda calculus introduces additional formulas to represent the denotations of specific parts of sentences, such as the verb phrase "loves Mary". In the lambda calculus, this could be formalized as , where the variable is a placeholder that can be filled by the denotation of whatever subject this verb phrase is combined with. The prefix binds the variable , notating the fact that this expression needs to be combined with an additional argument in order to express a complete proposition. This denotation can be combined with its subject argument using the rule of β-reduction.[32]

A crucial idea is that expressions belong to different types, which describe how the expressions can be used and combined with other expressions. Type theory, typically in the form of the typed lambda calculus, provides a formalism for this endeavor. It begins by defining a small number of basic types, which can be fused to create new types.[33]

According to a common approach, there are only two basic types: entities () and truth values (). Entities are the denotations of names and similar noun phrases, while truth values are the denotations of declarative sentences. All other types are constructed from these two types as functions that have entities, truth values, or other functions as inputs and outputs. This way, a sentence is analyzed as a complex function made up of several internal functions. When all functions are evaluated, the output is a truth value. Simple intransitive verbs without objects are functions that take an entity as input and produce a truth value as output. The type of this function is written as , where the first letter indicates the input type and the second letter the output type. According to this approach, the sentence "Alice sleeps" is analyzed as a function that takes the entity "Alice" as input to produce a truth value. Transitive verbs with one object, such as the verb "likes", are complex or nested functions. They take an entity as input and output a second function, which itself requires an entity as input to produce a truth value, formalized as .[e] This way, the sentence "Alice likes Bob" corresponds to a nested function to which two entities are applied. Similar types of analyses are provided for all relevant expressions, including logical connectives and quantifiers.[35]

Others

[edit]

Possible worlds are another central concept used in the analysis of linguistic meaning. A possible world is a complete and consistent version of how everything could have been, similar to a hypothetical alternative universe. For instance, the dinosaurs were wiped out in the actual world but there are possible worlds where they survived. Possible worlds have various applications in formal semantics, usually to study expressions or aspects of meaning that are difficult to explain when referring only to entities of the actual world. They include modal statements about what is possible or necessary and descriptions of the contents of mental states, such as what people believe and desire. Possible worlds are also used to explain how two expressions can have different meanings even though they refer to the same entity, such as the expressions "the morning star" and "the evening star", which both refer to the planet Venus. One way to include possible worlds in the model-theoretic formalism is to define a set of all possible worlds as one additional component of a model. The interpretation of the meanings of different expressions is then modified to account for this change. For example, to explain that a sentence may be true in one possible world and false in another, one can interpret its meaning not directly as a truth value but as a function from a possible world to a truth value.[36]

Situation semantics is a theory closely related to possible world semantics. Situations, like possible worlds, present possible circumstances. However, unlike possible worlds, they do not encompass a whole universe but only capture specific parts or fragments of possible worlds. This modification reflects the observation that many statements are context-dependent and aim to describe the speaker's specific circumstances rather than the world at large. For example, the sentence "every student sings" is false when interpreted as an assertion about the universe as a whole. However, speakers may use this sentence in the context of a limited situation, such as a specific high school musical, in which it can be true.[37]

Dynamic semantics interprets language usage as a dynamic process in which information is continually updated against the background of an existing context. It rejects static approaches that associate a given expression with a fixed meaning. Instead, this theory argues that meaning depends on the information that is already present in the context, understanding the meaning of a sentence as the change in information it produces. This view reflects the idea that sentences are usually not interpreted in isolation but form part of a larger discourse, to which they contribute in some way.[38] For example, update semantics—one form of dynamic semantics—defines an information state as the set of all possible worlds compatible with the current information, reflecting the idea that the information is incomplete and cannot determine which of these worlds is the right one. Sentences introducing new information update the information state by excluding some possible worlds, thereby decreasing uncertainty.[39][f]

Studied linguistic phenomena

[edit]

Quantifiers

[edit]

Quantifiers are expressions that indicate the quantity of something. In predicate logic, the most basic quantifiers only provide information about whether a condition applies to all or some entities, as seen in sentences like "all ravens are black" and "some students smoke". Formal semanticists use the concept of generalized quantifiers to extend this basic framework to a broad range of quantificational expressions in natural language that usually provide more detailed information. They include diverse expressions such as "most", "few", "twelve", and "fewer than ten".[41]

Most quantificational expressions can be interpreted as relations between two sets.[g] For instance, the sentence "all ravens are black" conveys the idea that the set of ravens is a subset of the set of black entities. Similarly, the sentence "fewer than ten books were sold" asserts that the set of books and the set of sold items have fewer than ten elements in common.[43] In English, quantifiers are often expressed with a determiner,[h] such as "all" and "few", indicating the relation between the sets, followed by a noun phrase and a predicate to describe the involved sets.[45]

Quantifiers can be divided into proportional and cardinal quantifiers based on the relation between the sets. Proportional quantifiers, such as "all" and "most", indicate the relative overlap of the first set with the second set. For them, the order of the sets matters. For instance, the sentences "all ravens are black" and "all black things are ravens" have different meanings even though they refer to the same sets. Cardinal quantifiers, such as "four" and "no", provide information about the absolute number of overlapping entities, independent of relative proportion. For them, the order of the sets does not matter, as exemplified by the sentences "no rose is black" and "no black thing is a rose".[46]

Typically, the domain of natural language quantifiers is implicitly limited to a certain range of entities relevant to the discussed issue. For example, in the context of a specific kindergarten, the domain of the sentence "all children are sleeping" is limited to the children attending this kindergarten.[47]

The scope of a quantifier is the part of the sentence to which it applies. Some natural language sentences have scope ambiguity, resulting in competing interpretations of the scope of quantifiers. Depending on how the scope is interpreted, the sentence "Some man loves every woman" can mean either "there is a man such that he loves all women" or "for every woman there is at least one man who loves her".[48]

Descriptions and names

[edit]
Black and white photo of a man wearing a dark suit, a white shirt, and a tie
Bertrand Russell analyzed the meaning of definite and indefinite descriptions using existential quantifiers.[49]

Definite and indefinite descriptions are phrases that denote a specific entity or group of entities within a given context. Definite descriptions in English typically use the definite article "the", followed by a noun phrase, such as "the president of Kenya". However, they can also take other forms, such as "her husband" or "John's bicycle". Indefinite descriptions are usually expressed with the indefinite articles "a" and "an", as in "a lazy coworker" and "an old friend".[50] Definite descriptions typically point to a unique entity and assume that the listener is familiar with the referent. Indefinite descriptions usually allow the description to apply to more than one entity and introduce the entity without presupposing prior knowledge.[51]

Diverse theories about the correct analysis of definite and indefinite descriptions have been proposed. An influential early view, suggested by Bertrand Russell, interprets them using existential quantifiers. It proposes that indefinite descriptions like "a man ran" have the logical form . Definite descriptions have a similar form, with the difference that the description is unique, meaning that the first predicate only applies to a single entity.[49] A central motivation for Russell's approach was to solve semantic puzzles that arise from definite descriptions that do not refer to any particular entity. For example, the sentence "the present king of France is bald" refers to no existing entity, posing challenges for determining its truth value. According to Russell's analysis, the sentence is false since no unique entity exists to which the predicates "present king of France" and "bald" apply.[52]

The problem of names is closely related to that of definite descriptions because both expressions aim to refer to a particular entity. According to Millian theories, names refer directly without any descriptive information of the denoted entity. This view is opposed by description theories, which argue that names carry implicit descriptive contents that help interpreters identify their referents. One view understands names as implicit definite descriptions, proposing that the descriptive content of the name "Socrates" may include information like "the teacher of Plato".[53]

Tense, aspect, and events

[edit]

Tense and aspect provide temporal information about events and circumstances. Tense indicates whether something happened in the past, present, or future, offering a reference point to place events within a timeline relative to the time of the utterance. Aspect conveys additional information about how events unfold in time, like the distinction between completed, ongoing, and repetitive events. In English, both tense and aspect can be expressed through verb forms. On the level of tense the sentence "I ate" indicates the past, whereas the sentence "I will eat" indicates the future. On the level of aspect, the sentence "I ate" indicates a completed action, whereas the sentence "I was eating" indicates an ongoing action.[54]

Formal semanticists employ diverse conceptual tools to describe tense, such as different types of temporal logic as extensions of predicate logic. One approach includes a set of times in the mathematical model to interpret temporal statements. Some models conceptualize time as a series of instances, while others introduce intervals as the basic units of time. The difference is that intervals have a duration and can overlap, whereas instances are discrete time points that do not intersect. One form of temporal logic introduces tense operators to indicate the time a sentence describes, like the operator for past events and the operator for future events. This way, the formula expresses that Naomi danced in the past, while asserts that she will dance in the future.[55] The semantic analysis of aspect is divided into grammatical aspect, expressed through verb forms, and lexical aspect, which covers the inherent temporal characteristics of different verbs.[56]

An influential approach to the semantic role of events was proposed by Donald Davidson. Using predicate logic, it represents events as singular terms and translates action sentences into logical formulas about events, even if the original sentences contain no explicit reference to events. For example, it translates the sentence "Jones buttered the toast slowly with a knife" as (literally: there was an event, which was a buttering of the toast by Jones, was slow, and involved a knife). One motivation for this approach is to provide a systematic method for translating adverbs, like "slowly", and other adjuncts into logical formulas.[57]

Intensionality, modality, and propositional attitudes

[edit]

Semanticists often distinguish two aspects of meaning: extension and intension.[58][i] Extension is the entity or group of entities to which an expression refers, while intension is the inherent concept or underlying idea it conveys. For example, the expressions "the morning star" and "the evening star" have the same extension, as both refer to the planet Venus. However, their meanings differ on the level of intension since they present the planet in different ways by evoking distinct concepts.[59]

Extensionality and intensionality[j] are characteristics of sentences. A sentence is extensional if expressions with the same extension can be substituted without changing the sentence's truth value. For example, the sentence "the morning star is a planet" remains true if the expression "the morning star" is replaced with the expression "the evening star". Intensional sentences, by contrast, are not only sensitive to extensions but also to intensions, meaning that extensionally equivalent expressions cannot be freely replaced. For instance, the sentence "Ann knows that the morning star is the morning star" is intensional since it can be true while the extensionally equivalent sentence "Ann knows that the evening star is the morning star" is false.[61]

Intensionality is present in various linguistic expressions. For instance, modal expressions, such as "may", "can", and "must", usually introduce intensional contexts.[k] They express what is possible or necessary, describing how the world could or could not have been rather than how it actually is. A common approach to the analysis of modal expressions is the use of the modal operators and to modify the meaning of sentences and represent what is possible and necessary. For example, if the formula stands for the statement "it is raining", then the formula stands for the statement "it is possible that it is raining". To interpret the meaning of modal statements, formal semanticists often rely on the concept of possible worlds. According to this approach, a sentence is possibly true if it is true in at least one possible world, whereas it is necessarily true if it is true in all possible worlds.[63][l]

Propositional attitude reports—another example of intensionality—discuss mental states of individuals. They often use verbs like "believes", "doubts", and "wants", followed by a that-clause describing the content of the attitude, like the sentence "Kyrie believes that the earth is flat". The use of possible worlds is also common for the analysis of propositional attitudes. For example, the content of a propositional attitude can be understood as the set of all possible worlds in which it is true, such as all possible worlds with a flat earth in the mentioned example.[65] The meaning of propositional attitude reports containing definite or indefinite descriptions is often ambiguous. This ambiguity arises from the interpretation of the description, which can be subjective or objective. For example, if Jasper wants a drink from his butler but is unaware that his butler poisoned his wife, then the sentence "Jasper wants a drink from the poisoner of his wife" is ambiguous. According to the objective interpretation—called de re interpretation—the sentence is true since the butler is in fact the poisoner. Conversely, the subjective interpretation—called de dicto interpretation—renders it false since Jasper does not want drinks from poisoners.[66]

Questions and imperatives

[edit]

The main focus of formal semantics is on statements, which aim to describe reality and are either true or false depending on whether they succeed. However, this analysis does not cover all types of sentences. Specific frameworks have been proposed for the analysis of other sentence types, such as questions and imperatives.[67]

Various theories analyze the meaning of questions in terms of possible answers, replacing the concept of truth conditions, common in the analysis of statements, with the related notion of answerhood conditions. One approach, initially formulated by Charles Leonard Hamblin, interprets answerhood conditions as the set of statements that qualify as answers to a question. For instance, the sentences "Marco called" and "Don called" qualify as answers to the question "Who called?", but the sentence "I like ice cream" does not. A common distinction is between yes-no questions, which only ask for confirmation, and open-ended questions, which seek more detailed information. Additional considerations include the distinctions between true and false answers, and between complete and partial answers, depending on whether the response contains all the requested information. On the symbolic level, questions can be expressed using as an operator to indicate the subject of the question. For example, the question "Who called?" can be formalized as , whereas the question "Did anyone call?" takes the form .[68]

Imperative sentences usually express commands or instructions, like the sentence "Close the door!". Unlike declarative and interrogative sentences, which generally convey or request information, the primary goal of imperatives is to influence the behavior of the listener. As a result, imperatives have no or at least no obvious truth conditions. Other difficulties in the analysis of imperative sentences are that they usually lack an explicit subject and that they can express various other meanings besides commands, such as advice, invitations, or permissions. Formal semanticists study the meaning of imperatives by examining how they interact with other linguistic phenomena. These include cases in which one imperative entails another imperative, the negation of an imperative, and conditional imperatives as well as conjunctions and disjunctions of several imperatives.[69]

Other phenomena

[edit]

Diverse other linguistic phenomena are studied in formal semantics. Negation is typically understood as an operation that inverts the meaning of an expression. In classical logic, it is expressed through the operator as in , indicating that Mia is not sleeping. This operator inverts the truth value of a statement: if is false then is true. In natural language, negative particles and quantifiers, such as "not" and "no", are often used to indicate negation. These expressions can occur in different positions within sentences to negate either the full sentence or specific parts of it. The scope of a negation operator is the part of the sentence that it affects, which can sometimes be ambiguous. For example, the sentence "all doctors have no car" can mean that not every doctor has a car, that not a single doctor has a car, or that no individual car is collectively owned by all doctors.[70]

Plural expressions refer to multiple objects, such as the terms "children" and "apples". Formal semanticists typically interpret them as denoting some kind of plural object, such as the set of individuals belonging to the group in question. They distinguish between distributive and collective uses depending on whether the predicate applies to each individual separately or to the group as a whole. Some sentences are ambiguous and allow for both interpretations. For example, the sentence "two boys pushed a car" can mean that there were two cars and each boy pushed one (distributive) or that there was one car that both boys pushed together (collective).[71]

Formal semanticists also examine expressions whose meaning depends on contextual factors. They include indexical or deictic expressions, which refer to some aspect of the situation of the text. Examples are the pronouns "I" and "you", which refer to the speaker and the addressee, as well as the adverbs "today" and "over there", which refer to temporal and spatial aspects of the situation. Anaphoric expressions are another type of context-dependent expression. They refer to terms or phrases used earlier in the text, called antecedents. In the passage "Peter woke up. He switched on the light." the word "he" is an anaphoric expression with the word "Peter" as its antecedent. This grammatical association is known as binding and depends on the context since the word "he" would refer to someone else if the preceding sentence had a different antecedent.[72] Other linguistic phenomena studied by formal semanticists include presupposition, conditionals, thematic roles, spatial expressions, adjectives, and adverbs.[73]

While much work focuses on the study of English sentences, formal semantics is not limited to the English language and includes cross-linguistic analysis.[74] For example, there are diverse methods of expressing grammatical aspect across distinct languages, including prefixes, verb endings, auxiliary verbs, or combinations of several methods. They impact semantic analysis by influencing the hierarchical structure of sentences.[75] Similar problems of cross-linguistic analysis are also found for other linguistic phenomena, including quantification and indefinite descriptions.[76]

Interfaces

[edit]

In formal semantics, interfaces are points of interaction between semantics and other branches of linguistic inquiry. They concern how diverse factors, such as grammar and the speaker intention, influence meaning.[77]

Syntax-semantics interface

[edit]
A syntax tree in which the sentence S is made up of a noun phrase NP and a verb phrase VP, which is itself made up of smaller constituents.

The meaning of a sentence depends in part on its syntactic structure. For instance, the sentences "John saw Mary" and "Mary saw John" contain the same words but have different meanings because they differ in their syntactic structure. Thus, theories of compositional semantics will provide interpretation rules that map syntactic trees to their meanings. The nature of these rules depends in part on which model of syntax is assumed. Many theories of semantics assume a generative model of syntax, such as Government and binding theory or minimalism, while other common approaches include categorial grammar and HPSG.[78]

In such theories, the interpretation system often uses rules such as the following. These rules specify how to start with a syntactic node and calculate its denotation, written . These rules are applied recursively.[79]

  • Terminal Node: If is a syntactic node with no daughters, then is specified in the lexicon.
  • Nonbranching Node: If is a node whose sole daughter is , then .
  • Function Application: If is a node with daughters and where is a function whose domain contains , then .

A major debate in the syntax-semantics interface concerns the proper treatment of apparent mismatches between form and meaning, particularly related to scope. One common approach posits a level of grammatical structure called logical form. In this view, sentences do not have a unique syntactic form, but rather a phonological form, which gets pronounced, and a separate logical form, which undergoes semantic interpretation. In these approaches, apparent mismatches between form and meaning can be explained using syntactic mechanisms such as movement. This is in contrast to approaches such as Direct Compositionality, which assume that the surface grammatical form is the only grammatical form and that mismatches should be explained using other semantic mechanisms such as type shifting. Empirical evidence informing this debate includes ACD, scope islands, and data from languages such as Hungarian which has been argued to "wear its LF on its sleeve".[80]

Semantics-prosody interface

[edit]

In many languages, semantic meaning is influenced by prosodic features such as intonation and stress. In particular, focus can affect the truth conditions of a sentence. For instance, in a context where Hannah gave Matt many gifts, the a-sentence below can be true while the b-sentence would be false. On the other hand, in a context where Hannah gave everyone a book, the b-sentence could be true while the a-sentence would be false.[81]

(1) a. Hannah only gave MATT a book. b. Hannah only gave Matt a BOOK.

To explain focus-sensitive phenomena, linguists commonly adopt enriched systems such as alternative semantics or structured semantics which provide a notion of a focus alternative.[82] Work at the semantics-prosody interface also addresses the meaning contributions of particular intonational tunes such as rising declaratives.

Semantics-pragmatics interface

[edit]

Pragmatics is the study of the parts of linguistic meaning which arise not through compositional semantics, but rather through reasoning about the speaker's intentions. For instance, the sentence "Steve invited Anne or Mary" typically conveys (i) that Steve invited one or the other and (ii) that he did not invite both. The first of these inferences is usually regarded as a semantic entailment, since it cannot be denied without contradicting the sentence. However, because the inference in (ii) can be denied without a contradiction, it is often regarded as a weaker pragmatic inference called an implicature.[83]

Traditionally, pragmatics has been viewed as a process of enriching the meanings computed by the semantics. On this view, the output of the semantics is taken to be part of the input to the pragmatics. For instance, the disjunctive example above is traditionally analyzed as semantically denoting an inclusive disjunction whose truth conditions are compatible with Steve having invited both. Then the implicature that he didn't invite both is derived by applying pragmatic reasoning to the question of why the speaker didn't say the more informative alternative "Steve invited Anne and Mary".[84]


In various fields

[edit]

Formal logic

[edit]

Formal logic studies the laws of deductive reasoning, focusing on entailment relations between premises and conclusions rather than linguistic meaning in general. It investigates rules of inference, such as modus ponens, which describe the logical structure of deductively valid arguments.[85] Formal logicians develop artificial languages, like the language of predicate logic, to avoid the ambiguities of natural language and give precise descriptions of the laws of logic.[86] Formal semantics plays a central role in this endeavor for applying these laws to natural language arguments. It helps logicians discern the logical form of everyday arguments, serving as a crucial step in translating them into logical formulas.[87]

Another key overlap between formal semantics and formal logic concerns the meaning of artificial logical languages. The semantics of logic examines the construction of mathematical models of formal languages, similar to the models used by formal semanticists to study natural language. These models typically include abstract objects to represent individuals and sets. The relation to formulas is established through an interpretation function that maps symbols to the abstract objects they denote.[88] A key aspect of this interface is the contrast between syntactic and semantic entailment.[m] A premise syntactically entails a conclusion if the conclusion can be deduced using rules of inference. A premise semantically entails a conclusion if the conclusion is true in every possible model where the premise is true.[90]

Computer science

[edit]

Computational semantics is an interdisciplinary field at the intersection of computer science and formal semantics. It studies how computational processes can be utilized to deal with linguistic meaning. A primary focus is the analysis of natural language sentences through computer-based methods to discern their logical structure, understand their content, and extract information. This form of inquiry has various applications in areas of artificial intelligence, such as automated reasoning, machine learning, and machine translation. Difficulties in this process come from the ambiguity, vagueness, and context dependence of natural language expressions.[91]

Another intersection concerns the analysis of the meaning of programming languages. A programming language is an artificial language designed to give instructions or describe computations to be performed by computers. A formal semantics of a programming language is a mathematical model of how it works. Its goal is to help computer scientists understand, analyze, and verify program behavior.[92] Static semantics describes the process of compilation or how a human-readable programming language is translated into binary machine code.[93] Dynamic semantics examines run-time behavior or what happens during the execution of instructions.[94] The main approaches to dynamic semantics are denotational, axiomatic, and operational semantics. Denotational semantics describes the effects of code elements, axiomatic semantics examines the conditions before and after code execution, and operational semantics interprets code execution as a series of state transitions.[95]

Cognitive science

[edit]

Cognitive science studies the mind by focusing on how it represents and transforms information. It is an interdisciplinary field that integrates research from diverse areas, ranging from psychology and neuroscience to philosophy, artificial intelligence, and linguistics.[96] Some researchers emphasize the central role of language in understanding the human mind and rely on formal semantics to provide an abstract model for analyzing how linguistic meaning is constructed and interpreted.[97]

Formal semantics is also relevant to cognitive neuroscience, which seeks to explain the biological processes underlying cognition. One approach uses brain imaging techniques to visualize brain activity and employs mathematical models to link this data to cognitive processes. Insights from formal semantics can refine these models and help formulate testable predictions. For instance, researchers can examine semantic cognition by presenting a person with semantic variations of a sentence and measuring the differences in brain responses.[98]

History

[edit]
Photo of a man with grey hair wearing a suit and a tie
Alfred Tarski developed a rigorous theory of truth in formal languages.[99]

Formal semantics has its roots in the development of modern logic in the late 19th and early 20th centuries. Gottlob Frege laid the foundations of predicate logic and examined how this logical system can be used to analyze natural language arguments. He engaged in this analysis using a small number of basic concepts of formal semantics, such as singular terms, predicates, quantifiers, and logical connectives. Frege also formulated the principle of compositionality and introduced the distinction between sense and reference.[25]

Following Frege's work, Alfred Tarski developed a rigorous theory of truth in formal languages starting in the 1930s. He provided a precise analysis of truth conditions and clarified the concept of logical consequence. His work formed a cornerstone of model theory.[99] Rudolf Carnap synthesized and generalized many of Frege's and Tarski's ideas. To overcome problems associated with extensional definitions of meaning, Carnap pioneered the study of intensional semantics, defining intensions as functions from possible worlds to denotations.[100]

Donald Davidson was influenced by Tarski's approach and emphasized the role of truth conditions as a key component of semantic theory and the analysis of sentence meaning. He also proposed an event-based formalism to translate action sentences into predicate logic.[101] Noam Chomsky's work on generative grammar inspired Jerrold Katz and Jerry Fodor to explore the relation between syntactic rules and semantic content through the principle of compositionality.[102]

Many of these contributions prepared the work of Richard Montague, usually considered the main founding figure of formal semantics. One of his key achievements, starting in the late 1960s and early 1970s, was the development of a systematic formalism for analyzing significant portions of the English language using tools from formal logic. This stood in contrast to many earlier approaches, which addressed some aspects of natural language but were skeptical of broader applications and had their main focus on the analysis of formal languages. Relying on type theory and the principle of compositionality, Montague analyzed complex natural language expressions as nested functions with precisely defined input and output types.[103] This development happened against the background of the "linguistic wars"—a debate between proponents of generative semantics and interpretive semantics about whether syntax and semantics are deeply integrated or independent aspects of language. Montague's approach aimed to provide a unified perspective by explaining the relationship between syntactic and semantic rules.[104] His system also covers intensional sentences such as modal expressions and propositional attitude reports through the concept of possible worlds.[105]

Barbara Partee integrated Montague's insights into linguistic theory.[106]

In the following decades, Montague's work influenced many scholars, who sought to refine or modify his insights and apply them to diverse linguistic phenomena.[107] Barbara Partee was instrumental in explaining and popularizing Montague's ideas, helping formal semantics grow into a subfield of linguistics by integrating Montague's insights into linguistic theory.[106] In response, various theorists focused on the relation between syntax and semantics, proposing diverse grammatical theories to explain the interface, such as Generalized phrase structure grammar and Head-driven phrase structure grammar. They also include the contributions of Irene Heim and Angelika Kratzer to the semantics of generative grammar.[108] A parallel development was a rising interest in pragmatics, which examines how the use of an expression affects its meaning, encompassing topics like context dependence, presupposition, and indexicality.[109]

The work of Robert Stalnaker and David Lewis prepared the development of dynamic semantics, which analyzes the meaning of a sentence as the information contribution it makes. Their theories inspired later developments by Hans Kamp, Heim, Jeroen Groenendijk, and Martin Stokhof.[110] Stalnaker and Lewis, together with Saul Kripke, also made influential contributions to possible world semantics.[111] Jon Barwise and John Perry proposed situation semantics as another influential framework. It incorporates many insights from possible world semantics but takes a more fine-grained approach, analyzing meaning in terms of situations rather than possible worlds.[112] Both David Kaplan and Pauline Jacobson made various contributions to the study of context-sensitive expressions, such as deictic and anaphoric terms. Jacobson also explored the principle of direct compositionality, which suggests a particularly close link between syntax and semantics.[113]

See also

[edit]

References

[edit]

Notes

[edit]
  1. ^ In this example, the entailment relation is one-way. However, entailments can also go in both directions if two sentences entail each other, like the sentences "Tina is tall and happy" and "Tina is happy and tall". In such cases, the two sentences are said to be equivalent.[11]
  2. ^ This general method also reflects the externalist theory of meaning common in formal semantics: the meaning of an expression is interpreted as the entities it denotes in an abstract model.[18]
  3. ^ This can be expressed symbolically through the use of double brackets. For example, the formula refers to the object denoted by the name "Tina" in the model "M".[19]
  4. ^ Typically, predicates start with uppercase letters and singular terms start with lowercase letters.[27]
  5. ^ This process is known as currying.[34]
  6. ^ Dynamic predicate logic is another approach that modifies the language of predicate logic to better capture natural language expressions that refer to individuals mentioned earlier, such as pronouns.[40]
  7. ^ In type theory, sets can be interpreted as characteristic functions from entities to truth values of the type , returning true if the entity is a member of the set and false otherwise. As a consequence, most quantifiers have the type , corresponding to a function that takes two sets as inputs and outputs a truth value that depends on the relation between the sets.[42]
  8. ^ In some cases, bare plurals act as quantifiers without a determiner, such as the sentence "firemen wear helmets", expressing the idea that all firemen wear helmets.[44]
  9. ^ This distinction is also discussed under the terms reference and sense as well as denotation and connotation.[58]
  10. ^ Intensionality is different from intentionality but the two concepts are related since expressions describing intentionality, like propositional attitude reports, are typically intensional.[60]
  11. ^ There are diverse ways to express modality, including modal auxiliaries such as "could" and "should"; modal adverbs such as "possibly" and "necessarily"; and modal adjectives such as "conceivable" and "probable".[62]
  12. ^ More fine-grained approaches distinguish between different types of modality, such as logical, epistemic, and deontic modality, while introducing separate operators for each type.[64]
  13. ^ These entailment relations are also referred to as deductive-theoretic and model-theoretic consequence.[89]

Citations

[edit]
  1. ^
  2. ^
  3. ^ Cable 2021, pp. 2, 4–5
  4. ^
  5. ^
  6. ^
  7. ^
  8. ^
  9. ^ a b
  10. ^
  11. ^ Winter 2016, p. 16
  12. ^ Winter 2016, p. 19
  13. ^
  14. ^
  15. ^ Cable 2021, pp. pp=6-17
  16. ^ Schlenker 2024, Section 1
  17. ^
  18. ^
  19. ^ Winter 2016, p. 18
  20. ^
  21. ^
  22. ^
  23. ^
  24. ^
  25. ^ a b
  26. ^
  27. ^ Shapiro & Kouri Kissel 2024, § 2.1 Building Blocks
  28. ^
  29. ^
  30. ^ Lappin 2003, pp. 371–375
  31. ^ Winter 2016, p. 55
  32. ^
  33. ^
  34. ^ Winter 2016, pp. 57–58
  35. ^
  36. ^
  37. ^
  38. ^
  39. ^
  40. ^
  41. ^
  42. ^
  43. ^
  44. ^ Westerst?hl 2016, pp. 210–211
  45. ^
  46. ^
  47. ^
  48. ^
  49. ^ a b Ludlow 2023, § 2. Russell's Theory of Descriptions
  50. ^
  51. ^ Abbott 2009, pp. 184–186
  52. ^
    • Kearns 2011, pp. 111–113
    • Ostertag 2009, pp. 195–196
    • Ludlow 2023, § 3. Motivations for Russell's Theory of Descriptions, § 5.1 The Challenge to Russell's Truth Conditions
  53. ^
  54. ^
  55. ^
  56. ^
  57. ^
  58. ^ a b
  59. ^ Fitting 2022, § 1. What Is This About?
  60. ^
  61. ^
  62. ^ Portner 2009a, pp. 1–2
  63. ^
  64. ^ Kearns 2011, pp. 79–82
  65. ^
  66. ^
  67. ^
  68. ^
  69. ^
  70. ^
  71. ^
  72. ^
  73. ^
  74. ^
  75. ^
  76. ^
  77. ^
  78. ^
  79. ^
  80. ^
  81. ^
  82. ^
  83. ^ Schlenker 2016, pp. 664, 668–671
  84. ^ Schlenker 2016, pp. 664, 668–671
  85. ^
  86. ^
  87. ^
  88. ^
  89. ^
    • Cook 2009, pp. 82, 176
    • McKeon, Lead section, § 3. Model-Theoretic and Deductive-Theoretic Conceptions of Logic
  90. ^
  91. ^
  92. ^
  93. ^
  94. ^
  95. ^
  96. ^ Portner 2005, pp. 216–217
  97. ^
  98. ^
  99. ^ a b
  100. ^
  101. ^
  102. ^ Partee 2010, pp. 6–8
  103. ^
  104. ^
  105. ^
  106. ^ a b Partee 2010, pp. 15, 31, 34–36
  107. ^
  108. ^
  109. ^
  110. ^
  111. ^
  112. ^ Portner & Partee 2002, p. 6
  113. ^

Sources

[edit]
人为什么会觉得累 排异是什么意思 根管是什么 猪肝补什么功效与作用 mc是什么
吃什么油最健康排行榜 梦见好多蛇是什么意思 风疹病毒igg阳性是什么意思 沐雨栉风是什么生肖 辞职是什么意思
没睡好头疼是什么原因 aqi是什么意思 男人左眼跳是什么预兆 肾病有什么症状男性 2月18号是什么星座
保险费率是什么 肱骨外上髁炎用什么药 声嘶力竭是什么意思 地球是什么星 狗感冒吃什么药
扁平疣吃什么药hcv7jop6ns0r.cn 下作是什么意思hcv7jop9ns8r.cn 什么木质手串最好hcv8jop1ns7r.cn 痰湿瘀阻是什么症状hcv7jop6ns9r.cn 药物过敏用什么药hcv8jop0ns1r.cn
湿疹是因为什么原因引起的hcv9jop6ns2r.cn 西米是用什么做的onlinewuye.com 脸过敏用什么药膏效果最好hcv8jop0ns1r.cn 梦到自己掉牙齿是什么预兆zhongyiyatai.com 比目鱼又叫什么鱼hcv9jop3ns3r.cn
虚火牙痛吃什么药效果最快hcv8jop8ns5r.cn 单飞什么意思jasonfriends.com 第一次什么感觉hcv9jop8ns1r.cn 畸胎瘤是什么xinjiangjialails.com 为什么指甲有竖纹hcv9jop2ns0r.cn
反胃吃什么可以缓解hcv9jop1ns8r.cn 工作室是干什么的hcv7jop6ns3r.cn 两个人在一起的意义是什么bysq.com 纳征是什么意思hlguo.com 孤寡老人国家有什么政策hcv7jop9ns8r.cn
百度